(navigation image)
Home American Libraries | Canadian Libraries | Universal Library | Community Texts | Project Gutenberg | Children's Library | Biodiversity Heritage Library | Additional Collections
Search: Advanced Search
Anonymous User (login or join us) Upload
See other formats

Full text of "Madhva Logic by Susil Kumar Maitra"

MADHVA LOGIC 



BEING AN ENGLISH TRANSLATION OF THE PRAMANA- 



i^*'"' 



CANDRIKA WITH AN INTRODUCTORY OUTLINE OF 
MADHVA PHILOSOPHY AND THE TEXT IN 

SANSKRIT 



BY 

SUSIL KUMAR MAITRA, M.A., Ph.D. 

Lecturer in Philosophy, University of Calcut^^£>, iVIJ&Y^ 
Author of "The Ethics of the HwdusJ^ 








PUBUSHED BY THE 

CALCUTTA UNIVERSITY 

1936 






■ _••-> 



* f'r-U 



-■•:■■■ ,*.'>«.■■..*■■.■; . ■ . 



MUNSHI RAM MANOHAR LAL 

Orieolei <u 1 oieign EooA-Sellers 
M- 1165; Nai Sarak, DELH1-6 



V#3 









_■ s — 






.■■I 



•A'-'/tf-'-A' c : ' >." 



PRINTED AND PUBLISHED BY BHTTJ'EKDRALAL BANEHJEE 
AT THB CALCUTTA UNIVERSITY PBE88, SENAT8 HOUSB, CALCUTTA. 



Beg. No. 686B.— October, 1936— B. 



fe 










■:.■*" 



3>- 



— — *-.y 



■■O* 



'1;" * 



.jS 



-*" * - '*- * 






■\ 




PEEFACE 

The accredited authority on Madhva Logic 
is Jayatlrtha, and his celebrated work, the 
Pramanapaddhati, is the authoritative logical text 
of " the Madhvas. The Pramanacandrika is a 
shorter work and follows the Pramayapaddhati 
closely, reproducing the language of the Paddhati 
in many places and acknowledging the Paddhati 
as its authority at the end of every section. 
The Gandrika however has the merit of being 
a clear presentation both of Madhva and other 
rival views. The present translation, it is hoped, 
will give a clear idea of Madhva logical theory 
and its points of agreement and disagreement 
with the theories of other schools. The Intro- 
duction which gives an outline of Madhva Phi- 
losophy will also be of use in understanding and 
correctly appraising the Madhva viewpoint. ^ 

Jayatlrtha is supposed to have flourised to- 
wards the middle of the fourteenth century. 
According to one estimate he must be placed 
between 1317 A.D. and 1380 A.D. Since the 
author of the Gandrika refers throughout to 
Jayatlrtha's Paddhati as his source-book, and 
always with profound respect, he may be taken 
to be one of Jayatlrtha's younger contemporaries. 



VI 



MADHVA LOGIC 



He must therefore have flourished either at the 
latter half of the 14th or the beginning of the 

15th -century. 

My sincerest thanks are due to my colleague, 
Dr. Satcowrie Mookerjee, for seeing the Sanskrit 
text through the Press. He has however departed 
from the original Madhva Vilasa edition (now 
out of print) in two respects. In the first place, 
he has divided the work into chapters-^an 
evident improvement in form. Secondly, he has 
changed the text itself in some places. As I am 
unable to accept the correctness of all the changes 
he has made, some of the passages as they occur 
in the original Madhva Vilasa edition appearing 
to me to be quite in order, I leave the whole 
matter to the judgment of my readers. 



-r -> -^f 



"*- * "l»-t 



*r ^* 



^ f* >- ," s«--r? : 



CONTENTS 




Introduction 



• » # 



PAGE 

ix-xxvi 



The English Transxmtion 



1-2 

3-6 

6-11 

11-12 

12-14 



On Liberation and the Means to Liberation 
On Uddeia or Statement 
On Lak§ana or Definition 
On Parik§d or Examination 
Definition of Pramana or Valid Evidence 
Definition of Samiaya or Uncertain Cognition 14-20 
Definition of Viparyyaya or Error 20-21 

Memory as Valid Knowing ... 21-22 

Pramana as defined by other schools 22-25 

Pramana as Kevalapramdw and Anupramma 25 
Four kinds of Kevalapramana ... ■ 26-36 

Anupramdna as Perception, Inference and . 

Authoritative Communication 

Definition of Perception 

Seven Kinds of Perception 

Definition of Inference 

Factors of Inference 

Invariable Concomitance as a Condition of 

Inference 63 ^ 7 

Different Kinds of Invariable Concomitance 57-61 
Concomitance as known makes Inference 
: Possible 61-62 



36-37 
37-39 
39-51 
51-52 
52-53 



vm 



MlDHVA logic 



' " < 



PAGE 



Invariable Concomitance how known 

Three Kinds of Inference 

Nyftya View of the Different Kinds 

Inference 
Fallacies of Inference 
Nyaya View of Hetu and the Fallacies 
Authority or Sgama defined 
Defects of Verbal Communications 
Words and Sentences as Costituents of 

Verbal Communications 
Learning of Word-meanings 
Primary and Secondary Functions of 

Words 

Agama as Personal and Impersonal 

The Evidential Value of Sgama 
Refutation of Arthupatti, Upamana, Anu- 

palabdhi, Sambhava, Aitihya, etc., 

as Independent Pramanas 
Intrinsic Validity and Extrinsic In- 

validity 



of 



63-64 
64-65 

65-83 

83-87 

87-100 

100-101 

101-109 

103-107 
107-109 
109-111 

111-112 

112-114 
115-122 



123-126 



* " * 



*. A 









INTRODUCTION 




Madhva philosophy is the conceptual formula- 
tion of the religious attitude of devotion or 
Bbakti and rests on the idea of an essential 
distinction between the devotee and the object 
of his worship. As the philosophic interpretation 
of the Vedanta teachings it is therefore not merely 
revolutionary but also heretical. Its dualistic 
metaphysics and its conception of the Lord as 
the efficient and not the material cause of the 
world are a direct negation of the monism of the 
Upanishadic teachings. It has thus been repu- 
diated by Vedantists themselves as a gross cari- 
cature of the Vedanta doctrines, particularly 
by the Sankarite Advaitins who reject even 
qualified non-dualism as inconsistent with Vedantic 
Absolutism. Madhvaism thus stands to orthodox 
Vedantism as Sufism does to Islamic Monotheism. 
If pantheistic Sufism is the worst heresy of 
Islamism, no less is Madhva Theism as an 
interpretation of Vedanta monism. 

The central conception in the Madhva meta- 
physics is the idea of an eternal and unsur^ 
mountable gap between the Lord and the world 
of inanimate objects and sentient souls. The 
Lord is the highest reality and has independent 
being.. The world and the individual souls axs 

B 



t MADHVA LOGIC 

all dependent on the Lord, but are not existent- 
ially one with Him. The Lord thus is the 
efficient and not the material cause of the world 
(c/. NyEya). The world depends on the Lord, 
but also has being outside Him. So also have 
the jivas or individual souls who are subservient 
to the Lord and are his eternal servants. Thus 
the distinctions between the Lord and the world 
and between the Lord and sentient souls are 
not merely essential but also eternal. 

The main points of the Madhva Philosophy 
are summarised in a Sanskrit sloka the purport 
of which we give here in English : — 

The Lord (Hari) is the highest reality (para- 
tattw). The world is real. Difference is real. 
Individual souls are the servants of the Lord 
(Hareranucardh). They are distinguished by 
superior and inferior excellences. Liberation is 
the experience of untainted innate bliss. Bhakti 
or devotion together with the Lord's grace is the 
means to liberation. Perception, Inference and 
Verbal Testimony are the sources of knowledge. 
In regard to the Lord the Vedas are the sole 
evidence. The Vedas are eternal and impersonal. 
■:; The above clearly brings out. the wide diver- 
gence of the Madhva and the Sankarite view&f 
For the Sankarite the world is a false appearance 
in the Absolute and is devoid of strict reality. 
For the Madhvas the world has reality, though 
po$ the self-dependent reality of the Lord, For 



IM-RODUCIION xi 

r 

w 

the Sankarites, distinction is an indescribable false 
appearance in the undifferenced reality of the 
Absolute. Hence the distinctive reality of the 
world is an eternally cancelled appearance in 
Brahman. For the Madhvas, distinction is not 
only real but also eternal. Hence the five dis- 
tinctions between the Lord and the inanimate 
world, between the Lord and the individual souls, 
between one individual soul and another, between 
one inanimate object and another and between 
an individual soul and an inanimate object are 

both real and eternal. 

This brings us to the Madhva view of the 
nature and constitution of the world and its 
scheme of the padarthas or knowables. Unlike 
the Nyaya-Vaisesikas who recognise seven kinds 
of knowables, the Bhattas who recognise five 
(the seven of the Nyaya-vaisesikas minus visesa 
and samavaya) and the Prabhakaras who recognise 
eight [five of the Nyaya-vaisesikas barring 
abhdva and viiesa, plus samkhya (number), 
s&dr&ya (similarity) and Sahti (potency)], the 
Madhvas recognise ten kinds of padarthas, viz., 
(1) substance, (2) quality, (3) action, (4) gene- 
rality, (5) individuality, (6) the qualified sub- 
stantive (visista), (7) the composite whole 
(amsi), (8) Power or Sakti, (9) Similarity and 
(10) Absence or Negation. 

>i Of these, substances are of twenty different 
kinds and comprise (1) The Supreme Soul or tb** 



Xll MADHVA LOGIC 



Lord, (2) Laksmi, the Lord's consort, (2) In- 
dividual Souls, (4) Unchanging Akasa which is 
the same thing as space, (5) Primordial Nature 
{Prakrii), (6) The Three Gums, (I) Mahat or the 
Great Principle, (8) Ahamkara or The Principle 
of Egoity, (9) Understanding (Buddhi), (10) 
Mind, (11) The Senses, (12) The Infra-sensibles 
(matra), (13) The Elements, (11) The Universe, 
(15) Nescience (Avidya)^ (16) The Alphabetical 
Sounds, (17) Darkness, (18) Kesidual Traces 
and Dispositions, (19) Time, (20) Reflection 
(Pratibimba). * 

Qualities again are of 41 different kinds 
including the qualities of the Nyaya-Vai&sikas 
as well as such other excellences and deficiencies 
as serenity, steadfastness, gravity of mind, fear, 
shame, strength, self-restraint, endurance, valour, 
magnanimity, etc. 

Actions again are either moral or non-moral. 
Moral actions are objects of approval or disapproval. 
Non-moraJ action is physical motion. 

Generality is either eternal or non-eternal. 

Individualities are innumerable and are the 
bases of all differentiation and distinction. 

By a qualified substance is meant a substantive 
specified by an adjective. 

Composite wholes are again either limited in 
size or of unlimited extent. 

Sakti or power is of four kinds, viz., inherent 
power, adventitious power, the power that is 







*c 



'# 



V5P 






INTRODUCTION Xl« 

unthinkable, and a word's power of meaning or 
referring to an object. 

Similarities are innumerable and are functions 
of single objects as determined by their relations 
to other objects. Thus though a similarity holds 
between one object and another, it is a function 
only of one and not of both. 

Absence is of four kinds, viz., Antecedent 
Absence, Emergent Absence, Absolute Absence 
and Reciprocal Absence. Of these the first are 
other than the locations they characterise. Not 
so reciprocal negation. It is the same as its locus, 
the negation being non-different from the entities 
which negate each other. Further it is either 
eternal or nou-eternal. As negation of eternal 
entities it is eternal, as negation of non-eternal 
entities it is non-eternal. This follows from such 
negation being non-different from the entities 
which so negate each other. Absolute negation 
is the negation of what never, nowhere exists. It 
is thus the negation of the unreal or the imaginary. 
Though the entity which it negates is unreal, the 
negation itself as the absolute absence of the unreal 
is real. Thus absolute negation is the real absence 
of the absolutely unreal. 

The Madhva view of the Lord and the indivi- 
dual soul presents many points of contact with, 
as well as of divergence from, the Nyaya view. Atf 
with the Naiy&yikas, the Lord, according to the 
Madhvas, is the efficient and not the material cause 



Xiv MADHVA LOGIC 

of the world. The Lord further is independent, 
all-pervading and is the subject of such qualities 
as omniscience, etc. Laksral is the power of the 
Lord. The jiva or individual soul, on the other 
hand, is atomic (contrast Nyaya), is existentially 
separate from, though dependent on, the Lord, is 
ignorant, in bondage, etc. Further the jiva stands 
to the Lord as reflection (pratibimba) to the 
original. Through the knowledge of the Lord the 
karmic potencies of the jiva wear away, and this 
prepares the way to. liberation. Bhakti together 
with the Lord's grace is the cause of Liberation 
which consists in the experience of pure, inherent 
bliss. Prakrti or primordial nature is the cause 
of bondage and is the root of beginningless 

* 

nescience. Nescience itself is a positive category 
and is the source of the two kinds of ignorance, 
viz., ignorance as regards one's own nature and 
ignorance as regards the nature of the Lord. 

The Madhva view of the twenty kinds of 
substance includes, it will be noted, not merely 
the nine different kinds of the Nyaya- Vaise$ikas 
but also .those of the Sankhya Philosophers. 
Elementary Akasa of the M&dhvas, e.g., is the 
same as the ikasa of the Nyaya-VaiSesikas, while 
unchanging Aka3a is only the space or dvik of the 
latter reintroduced under a different name. Thus 
we have all the nine of the latter, viz., the five 
elements, besides space, time, mind and self. But 
in addition to these we have also some of the 



INTRODUCTION XV 

Sankhya metaphysics. For example, Prakrti, the 
Gums, Buddhi, Ahamkdra, mind, the senses 
(indriya), the infrasensibles {maira corresponding 
to tanmatra), etc., are all Sankhya padarthas. To 
these of the Nyaya-Vaisesika substances and the 
Sankhya padarthas, the Madhvas add some of their 
own such as Avidyd (Nescience), Pratibimba (Eeflec- 
tion), the Alphabetical Sounds and Darkness. 

As regards gums as qualities, it will be noted 
that they are not the same as the three gunas 
which are substances. The gunas as qualities are 
attributes while the three gunas are substantive 
reals. The gunas as qualities, it will be further 
noted, include not only the Nyaya-VaiSe§ika 
qualities but also many moral attributes of the soul 
such as serenity, mental gravity, magnanimity, etc. 
Tbl Nyaya-Vai^esikas will regard these latter as 
compounds of certain primary qualities of the self 
such as pleasure, pain, attraction, aversion, etc 

The Madhva classification of actions 

and the morally indifferent or neutral alsj 
clear departure from the Nyaya-Vais* 
For the Nyaya-Vaise§ikas willing is a qi 
soul and not an action — a quality pj 
attraction or aversion as its condition anl 
being the object of moral judgment. 
ism however willing is regarded as a kind of acting 
and therefore as a species of the genus which 
includes physical motion as well. ._....: 

* . The Nyaya-VaiSe§ika view of generality is also 




xvi msbhva logic 

similarly modified by the Madhvas. The Naiya- 
yikas consider nityatm or eternality to be part of 
the definition of 'generality,' so that a 'generality' 
which is not nitya is no generality. The Madhvas 
reject this view and subscribe to the conception of 
nitya and anitya generalities. Thus Brahminhood, 
manhood, etc., are non-eternal generalities, since 
their individual substrates are non-eternal. A man 
may become a Brahmin through the practice of 
penance and self-mortification just as contrariwise 
one may lose Brahminhood through misdeeds, fio 
also manhood may be lost in a subsequent birth, 
it being possible for a man to be reborn as an 
animal in a subsequent rebirth. Thus we must 
suppose non-eternal generalities in such cases. 
But a generality like that of individual self-hood 
(fivatva) is eternal, for no jiva ever ceases to be£ 

And what is true of generality also holds of 
particularity. Here also we must recognise, 
according to Madhvas, both eternal and non- 
eternal particularities. Thus the particularity of 
an eternal spirit like the Lord is itself eternal -, 
while the particularity of a non-eternal thing like 
a jar is non-eternal. The Nyaya-Vaisesikas will 
say that the particularity of a non-eternal thing 
being due to the particularities of their eternal 
constituents, no separate particularity for the. 
whole as a compound need be assumed. But tbis 
view does not appeal to the Madhvas. . g 

In place of the samavaya relation of the Nyaya* - 



-'4 



vU 



INTRODUCTION XV11 

Vaisesikas, again, the Madhvas will have the two 
padarthas of the viiista or qualified substantive and 
the amsl or composite whole. These two between 
themselves comprise, according to the Madhvas, 
every case of the so-called constitutive relation of 
samavaya. 

Sakti, power, and Sadrsya, similarity, are not 
admitted as distinct padarthas by the Nyaya- 
Vai&sikas. They are however recognised as such 
by the Prabhakara Mimamsakas and the Madhvas 
agree with the Prabhakaras in this respect. 3akti 9 
however, according to Madhvas, includes, besides 
the power in words to refer to their meanings or 
objects, the unthinkable power which exists in 
the Lord alone in its completeness and only 
partially and in different degrees in other beings, 
the adventitious power 'which is generated in an 
idol or image through the inspiring influence-^ 
the worshipper's devotion and the inhe^nt <>r 
innate powers of things. Similarity agaiji , |£ 
eternal or non-eternal like generality and part^ 
cularity- Thus the similarity of jivas or individual 
souls and other eternal substances such as the Lord 
is eternal, but the similarity of non-eternal things 

VII 

.like jars, cloths, etc., is itself non-eternal. 
['- As regards Abhava or Absence, the Madhvas 
hold that it has reality though the pratjuogi^ 
cpuntei>entity of the ahpwe in some eap^gr 
■'f.Jwfc.. or unreal (e,flf., ?Dt absolute absence).^||g 
A ibe NJ^ygyjkas hojsevfi* -Ahhaxa has 

:■■: ■'•:? l V-~ '■■ ;;':-v:.v'- ■■■ : .,~, ■■■'■■ ■. ■■. '• . .'. 




XViii MADHVA LOGIC 

or objectivity but not saliva or reality. Abhava 
presupposes reality (bhava) being adjectival to it, 
but is not itself reality. Thus reality (bhavatva) 
appertains to the six positives or bhava-paddrthas, 
the first three (substance, quality and action) being 
real through the universal of being inhering in 
them (sattayogena sat) while the second three 
(generality, particularity and inherence) being real 
through relation to that in which reality inheres 
(ekartha-samavaya) . For the Madhvas however, 
'absence' or negation is a form of sattva or reality 
just as is 'presence.' According to them, padarthas 
include both the real and the unreal, the latter 
being a paddrtlia or knowable without reality (e.g., 
sky-flower, hare's horn, etc.). Reality again 
is either independent or dependent reality, the 
former being the Lord Himself and the latter 
including all positives (bhavah) and all negatives 
(abhavah) other than the Lord. Thus negation, 
according to the Madhvas, is a form of dependent 
reality though the entity negated in the case of 
absolute negation is the unreal or the imaginary. 
The Madhva, the Sankara-Vedanta and the Naya- 
Vai3e§ika views of absence thus present many in- 
teresting points of agreement and difference. For 
the Sankarites 'absence' has objectivity like its 
opposite 'presence' and as such presupposes the 
reality of the consciousness in which it appears. It 
however does not affect the latter just as the snake- 
appearance does not affect the nature of the rope 



INTRODUCTION XIX 

which is its substrate. Thus absence as objective 
appearance presupposes a substrate of reality but 
is not adjectival to the latter. For the Naiyayikas 
however absence as objective not merely pre- 
supposes reality but also determines or characterises 
it. Hence absence though itself not a form of 
positivity yet both presupposes and infects the 
' latter. For the Madhvas however 'absence' is 
itself a kind of dependent reality to be distinguished 
from the kinds which positively fill experience. 

We shall now close our survey of the Madhva 
Philosophy with a brief statement of the distinctive 

features of the Madhva Logic. 

if 

Pramam, according to the Madhvas, is either 

kevalapramana or Anupmmana. Kevalapramana is 

the knowledge which has pramanya through itself 
as valid knowledge of objects. Anupmmana is 
pramam as the conditioning process or activity 
which gives rise to self-validating knowledge- 
Thus kevalapramana is prama or valid knowledge 
regarded as being its own pramdna or evidence 
(cf. Eamanuja, Prabhakara), while Anupramdna is 
evidence through conditioning or causing the result- 
ing self-evidencing knowledge. 

Anupramdnas are of three kinds, viz., Percep- 
tion, Inference and Verbal Testimony. 

Of these, Perception is of seven kinds, viz., 
the five kinds of external perception by the external 
senses, internal perception by the mind and 
perception through the Witnessing Intelligence 



•A s 



- o 



XX MADHVA LOGIC 

which is the seventh kind of Perception. Smrti, ■, 
Recollection, is a form of internal perception : it 
is an immediate presentation of the past through 
the instrumentality of the mind. The impressions-:^ 
or residual traces of the past experience are the- j 
connecting link between the past experience and; ;j 
the present mental function. The recollection is- 1 
the insertion of the past into the present (c/. ; :| 
Bergson). 

The Madhva view of witnessing knowledge 
(gaksijridna) as a form of perception is peculiar. 
The knower itself acting as an instrument of 
knowledge is the Saksl or Witnessing Intelligence^ 
and the knowledge which results through the 

instrumentality of the latter is perception. 'Tttei 

w 

objects of such perception include the intrinsi 
nature of the self, the self's properties or attributes 
such as pleasure, etc., avidya or nescience, the^ 
functions of the mind such as the cognitions of 
the external sense (which are also cognised by% 
the mind), pleasure, pain, etc. Thus what other < 
schools will regard as objects of internal perception*! 
are here regarded as being . perceptions of 
witnessing subject. But as perceptions sucfc 
witnessing cognitions will be generated events! 
and will thus lack the timelessness involvedui$S| 
the witnessing consciousness of temporal mental 
events as temporal. This is why Sankarites 
that the witnessing consciousness is a kind 
pra tyak§a or perception . According to 



i£*! 




INTRODUCTION XXI 

it is primary (anubhutirupa) but is not a generated 
cognition being nitya or timeless. 

As regards inference, the Madhvas bold that 
the vyapii which mediates inferential reasoning 
may be one of four kinds, viz., samavyapti (a 
symmetrical invariable relation — corresponding to 
Hamilton's U propositions) , vimnavyapti (an 
asymmetrical invariable relation — corresponding 
to A propositions), of the form of mutual exclusion 
or parasparaparihara (corresponding to E proposi- 
tions), or parasparasamavesa, mutual overlapping, 
along with parasparaparihara, mutual exclusion 
[answering at once to the three propositions, 
(i) In some case at least where A is, B also is, 

(it) In some case at least where A is, B is not, and 
{Hi) In some case at least, where B is, A is not. 
The relation, e.g., between 'being a male' and 
? being a cook ' illustrates this form.] Further, 
according to the Madhvas, co-presence of the 
prolans (hetu) and the probandum (sadhya) either 
temporally or spatially is not necessary for valid 
inference. Hefcce the existence of the probans 
in the subject of the inference need not be always 
insisted on. When, e.g., one infers rain on the 
top of the hill from the perception of the fullness 
of the rivers at the base, the mark or hetu is the 
"fuHness of rivers," and that which is inferred 
hj< means of this, hm#, M., the sadhya ^ 
prob(mdmn r is "rain.-; But the place or 
z&m m&k wfmdd^h the #afe ? av i^i 




XX11 MADHVA LOGIC 



of the inference is the hill-top, while the mark 
or hetu, viz., 'fullness of rivers,' is observed not 
on the hill-top but at the base of the hill. Hence 
the Madhvas conclude, what is necessary for 
producing valid inference is not the observed 
copresence of probans and probandum, nor the 
observed existence of the probans in the inferential 
subject, but observation of the mark in any 
suitable place and time (samucitadeiadivrtti) . The 
mark in the above inference exists in the present 
time while what is inferred therefrom, viz., 'rain' 
belongs to the past. Similarly the mark is observed 
at the base while the rain which is inferred belongs 
to the hill-top. 

It may be pointed out however that this is no 
innovation of the Madhvas and cannot be regarded 
as one of the Madhva contributions to logical 
theory. The point was anticipated by the Mimam- 
sakas long before the Madhvas. Parthasarathi 
in the " Nyayaratnamala " discussing the nature 
of vydpti rejects the view that as a condition of 
inference it implies the copresence of the hetu 
and the sadhya as an indispensable condition. 
Smoke, e.g., which is rising up in the sky above 
proves fire not in the sky above but on the ground 
below. What is necessary therefore for inference 
is not spatial or temporal copresence of hetu and 
sadhya but simply fixed relation or niyama between 
them. Thus the way in which a thing is cognised 
in fixed relation to something else, in that way 



INTRODUCTION 




does it produce the cognition of its ct 
when cognised again (c/. " Nyayaratnamala" 
p. 57, Chowkhamba edition, 1900). The so-called 
Madhva contribution in this respect is therefore no- 
thing but a re-statement of the Miraamsaka view. 

The Madhva rejection of vyaiirekivyapti as a 
condition of inference is also no innovation of 
the Madhvas. The same view is also taken both 
by Mimamsakas and Sankarites long before the 
Madhvas, and the Madhva view in this respect 
is only a reproduction of earlier views. The 
Madhvas however may legitimately claim their 
classification of inference to be an improvement on 
earlier logic. Thus, according to them, inference 
is either from cause to effect or from effect to 
cause or from one thing to another not related 
to it as cause or effect. For the Buddhist such 
non-causal relation is nothing but the relation 
of co-essentiality between genus and species 
(tadatmya). But Naiyayikas hold that there are 
other such relations besides co-essentiality. The 
Madhva view of non-causal inferences combines 
in itself both the Buddhist and the Nyaya view- 
points and has thus the merit of being a simplified 
solution of the different issues. 

As regards Agama, ct authoritative verbal testi- 
mony, the Madhvas hold that it is both personal 
and impersonal. Thus the Vedas are authorita- 
tive evidence though devoid of a personal source. 
But so also are the personal communications 



xx i v MADHVA LOGIC 

recorded in the Mahabharata and other sacred 
works. In connection with Igama, the Madhvas 
discuss the question whether words mean common 
characters or denote individuals, and the Madhvas 
decide for the dual character ot the objective 
reference with the reservation however that in 
the case of nouns or substantives the primary 
reference is to an individual or individuals, while 
in the case of adjectives, verbs, etc., it is some 
attribute or character that is primarily meant. 
The psychology of learning word-meanings is also 
discussed by the Madhvas in this connection, 
and the view which they advocate in this respect 
is that the process of learning word-meanings 
consists in a course of parental guidance by means 
of uttered words accompanied by gesture-indic%yi 
tions of the objects meant. The Madhvas reject 
the Nyaya view of naming as a process o|: 
upamuna based on the instruction of elders. ...^ 

In regard to validity and its opposite invalidity! 
the Madhvas hold independent views though 
apparently agreeing with the Mimamsaka theory 
of intrinsic validity and extrinsic invalidity. Thus 
intrinsic validity, the Madhvas argue, is intru^| 
sicality in respect of utpatti (origination) or intrjag 
sicality in respect of subjective acceptance 1S| 
recognition (jnapti). Intrinsicality in respect 
origin means that the validity arises from 
same conditions as the cognition itself which;* 
characterises. And intrinsicality in respect 






:tt 



. ?ft 



INTRODUCTION . XXV 

subjective recognition means that the agency that 
cognises the cognition is also the agency that 
cognises the validity of the cognition. Now as 
regards intrinsicaUty in respect of origin, the 
Madhvas agree with the Mimamsakas and reject 
the NySya view of an additional efficiency in the 
causal conditions as a condition of the validity 
of the valid cognition. As regadrs subjective re- 
cognition of the validity, the Madhvas hold how- 
ever that intrinsicaUty here arises from the fact 
that the witnessing Intelligence that cognises the 
'..cognition is also the agency that cognises the 
validity. This is a clear departure from the 
Mimamsfc view, according to the Mimamsakas 
(BhSfctas) neither the cognition nor its validity 
being cogqised by any witnessing Intelligence, 
both being cognised inferentiatly by the self from 
the mark of knowoness in the object- As regards 
invalidity, again, the QXfirinsicality m.y.r^spect 
of origin consists, according to Madras, inits 
wising foocn the presence of certain defects in 
addition to the conditions, of cpgnition, while 
^trittsicaUty in respect of invalidation or sub- 
jective rejection consists in the cognition itself 
being cognised by one agency, viz., the Witnessing 
Intelligence and its invalidity being cognised 
otherwise, i.e., inferentiaUy from the mark of 
its practical failure, This also is an evident 
departure from the ordinary MimamsS view ac- 
onr<\\ n « to whir.h iasalidation comes either through 



XXVi MADHVA LOGIC 



1 



the perception of defects in the causal conditions 
or through the consciousness of discrepancy with 

other experiences. '' J 

It may be added here that the Madhva theory of / 
falsity comes nearer the Buddhist than the Nyaya. 
or Sankara-Vedanta views. Thus the Madhvas >• 
reduce the false to the level of the imaginary and , 
the unreal so that what the illusory experience 
apprehends is an absolute nought and not any 
elsewhere, elsewhen reality (as Naiyayikas say), 
nor any indescribable positivity without reality 
(as Sankarites say). Further, correction as ab- i 
solute negation is the cancellation or rejection of ? 

this absolute unreality. Thus absolute negation " ; k 

is the negation of a sheer nothing and not that 7.3 
of an elsewhere, elsewhen real something as | 
Naiyayikas say. For the Naiyayikas negation :A 
is always the exclusion of a real something from 
some real locus so that a negation of the unreal^ 
is sheer non-sense. The Judgment : '* The square- * 
circle is not" is, according to Naiyayikas, equiva- 
lent to the Judgment : "The square is not a circle/* q 
though expressed differently. For the Madhvas 
however the object of absolute negation is the g 
unreal or the imaginary so that the Judgment does 
not assert the exclusion of circle from square (as | 
Naiyayikas say) but expresses the absolute unreal- ■ 
ity of a square which is a circle as well. 1 

- , : . - ■■ • M 

' • • - 1 -. f v- , . . ; 



MADHVA logic 

ENGLISH TRANSLATION 

OF THE 

PRAMANACANDRIKA 

m 
a . j * 

- - pakt i ; 

Reverence to the God with the Horse's neck, 
the God who has LaksmI as his consort and who 
incarnated Himself in Rama— the God of Hanu- 
mana, in Krsija — the God of Bhima, and 
in Vedavyasa— the God of Madhva. Om HarL v 
,. Having touched the lotus-feet of the Lord of 
Lak§mi and also those of my Guru or Preceptor, 
I. proceed to write this 'Pramanacandrika 1 for 
the easy comprehension (even) of young, immature 

learners. 

Everybody on this earth desires that happiness 
alone shall be his lot and that not even the smallest 
unhappiness shall ever mar his life. This is the 
moksa or liberation that is sought by all. Since 
this freedom or liberation comes only from the 
knowledge of the absoluteness and independence 



MADHVA LOGIC 



-**v: 



'■A' 



:-u 



of the Lord and the dependence or subservience 
of everything else, it behoves every seeker of this J 
freedom (moksa) to understand all things in this 
way as being essentially subservient to or 
dependent on the power of the Lord who is in- 
dependent and absolute. Thus the commentator 
observes, he that realises all these that are 
dependent as being subject to the control of the 
Lord becomes liberated from the bonds of the 
empirical life. The knowledge of the dependent y 
and the independent however comes from valid '""1 
cognition and this is the reason why this 
particular treatise has been undertaken with the 
object of ascertaining the nature of valid cogni- 
tion. Even though the master Jayatlrtha has 
elaborately expounded the distinguishing marks of j 
valid cognition and the rest in such works as the^l 
Paddhati, etc. (Pramawpaddhati), yet, inasmuch ;| 
as these works are not easily intelligible to ; 
persons of feeble intelligence on account of theif 
deep and thoughtful language in which they are ; 
expressed, this treatise has been undertaken with| 
a view to make the doctrines intelligible to thestf] 
readers of average intelligence. And thus this 
undertaking is not superfluous even though it 
discusses most of the topics already discussed i%: 
these other works and gives besides a brief account 
of some of the objects of valid cognition as well. 
Since the (scientific) knowledge of Praman 
and other allied things presupposes the tria 



",' 






PRAMAtfACANDRIKA 3 

statement (uddeia), definition (laksana) and 
examination (pariksa), the definition of statement 
and the rest is therefore first of all set forth. 

UddeSa is the statement or verbal indication 
of the subject-matter by means of its name only. 

i In this definition the word 'udde&a' stands for 
what is defined and the rest constitutes its defini- 
tion, viz., the words ' verbal indication of the 
subject-matter by means of its name only.' This 
procedure (in regard to the thing defined and the 
definition thereof) will also be observed in all 
other cases (of definition) that will come up later 
on. If we say that a sound as such is a verbal 
indication, the babbling sound of the Ganges will 
rank as a verbal indication and thus our definition 
will be too wide. To exclude such cases we 
include the word indication in our definition. 
A verbal indication implies indication by 
alphabetical sounds (and not by sounds as such 

'" which may include non-alphabetical sounds such 
as the babble of a river) . But if we stop here 

:- and say that an alphabetical sound as such is a 
verbal indication, the alphabetical sounds 'the 
son of a barren woman' should pass as a verbal 
indication. Hence to exclude such nonsensical 
combinations of alphabetical sounds the word ; 
* subject-matter ' (in ' indication of the subject- 

i? matter') has been included in the definition. 

% (The words 'son of a barren woman' ar^ift^^ 
iT,^««« M «f anvthitisr and therefore indicate 



* 



* 



i : MIDHVA LOGIC 

subject-matter.) But if we stop here and accept % 
' verbal indication of the subject-matter ' as a ^ 
logically complete definition (of uddeso), the | 
* caw ' ' caw ' of the crow will pass as a statement 
or Uddeia. (The 'caw* 'caw' of the crow is a 
combination of alphabetical sounds and it also 
indicates something that really exists, viz*» the 
crow's voice.) Hence the words 'by the name* 
in the definition which mean * by the words of 
the sacred language.' Even so, the definition , 
is too wide applying as it does to a sentence like 
'The earth has the character of smell' which 
amounts to a definition (and not to a verbal indica- 
tion of the subject-matter only). To exclude such 
cases, the word ' only * has been added (in ' by the 
name only '). The meaning is : the name which 
indicates the subject-matter in a statement is not "| 
used with a view to bring out the distinguishing % 
marks of the subject-matter. (The name is used 
only to indicate the subject-matter and not to de- 
fine it.) In the case of the sentence 'The earth 
has the quality of smell ' which amounts to a defi- 
' .nition, though the subject-matter is indicated 
by means of the words (names) of the sacred i 
language, yet, since the words have not been 
selected without reference to the marks which 
distinguish or define the subject-matter, the 
sentence cannot rank as a mere statement. 
Hence our definition of statement (as givefi| 
above) is not too wide. Hence we conclude : a 



-S 

.11 \ 

"as 



'J'u 















PRAMA^ACANDRIKA 5 

statement consists in the indication of a subject- 
matter by means of such words (names) of the 
Sanskrit language as do not refer to the marks 
which distinguish or define the subject-matter in 
question . 

Some hold that the word 'only' has been 
added (in the above definition of Uddeia) with a 
view to exclude only such definitions as * The earth 
has the quality of smell.' For (according to them) 
an Udde£a is a statement of the subject-matter 
without reference to its specifying or uncom- 
mon properties. Thus in the sentence (which 
is, in effect, a definition) .' The earth has 
the quality of smell,' since the subject-matter 
is indicated by reference to an uncommon 
property, viz., the possession of odour, the 
condition of indication of the subject, 
without reference to any uncommon 
of it is wanting, and thus our defi] 
not applying to it) is not too wide, 
be said that in the case of the earth 

4 

things, statements in this sense are impol 
so far as such statements will have to 
their respective subject-matters through the un« 
common properties of earthiness and the rest that 
distinguish them. For what is meant (by a verbal 
indication without reference to the uncommon 
properties of the subject-matter) is merely that the 
statement should not contain any reference to dis- 
tinctive or uncommon properties other than those 




6 MADHVA LOGIC 

that constitute the bare property of being the sub- 
ject-matter in question. 

This however is not a correct interpretation 
of our definition, for the definition as thus inter- 
preted will apply to sentences which are in the 
nature of definitions such as ' The earth has the 
property of earthiness ' and thus will be too wide. 
('The earth has the property of earthiness ' is a 
verbal definition and not a statement of a subject- 
matter.) The sentence ' the earth has the property 
of earthiness ' indicates a subject-matter (viz., the 
earth) without reference to any uncommon proper- 
ties other than those that constitute the bare i 
property of being the subject-matter in question f 
(i.e., the property of earthiness). 

(Having explained the nature of Uddeia, :i 
we now proceed to define Laksana or definition.) > .:'"- 

A defining mark (laksaya) is an attribute 
that exists only in the thing defined (and not in \ 
anything else), This means that a defining mark v 
is an attribute that exists in every instance of 
the thing defined and does not exist in anything . ■ 
else. Thus in the case of the cow, the ' posses- \£ 
sion of a dewlap' serves as a defining mark ■-.-] 
as it exists only in (all) animals that are v 
cows and does not exist in animals that are not 

COWS. .-•". ;■*■£ 

* llYf,ll 

If we say that an attribute as such is al 
defining mark, the ■ possession of undivided hoofs * 
will pass as a definition (of the cow) and thus 






prama^tacandrikI 7 

our definition of a defining mark will be too wide. 
(Possession of undivided hoofs is an attribute, 
but it is not an attribute of the cow which has 
cloven hoofs.) Hence we insist on the existence 
of the attribute in the thing defined. 

If we stop here and rest content with saying 
that a defining mark is an attribute that exists 
in the thing defined, then the ' possession of 
mixed colour ' will pass as a definition of the cow 
and thus our definition of a defining mark will 
be too wide. (Mixed colour exists in some cows 
but not in all cows and therefore cannot be a 
definition of the cow.) To exclude such attri- 
butes (as do not exist in every instance of the 
thing defined) we say the attribute (that is, a 
t defining mark) must exist in every instance of 

the thing defined. - 

But this also does not suffice, for 'possession 
of horns' may pass as a defining mark (of the 
cow) as thus interpreted and thus our definition-: 
becomes too wide. (Possession of horns can*: 
not be a defining mark of the cow, for though 
this attribute may exist in every instance 
-of a cow, yet it exists also in other animals 
such as the goat, the dear, etc) To exclude 
such attributes (as exist both in the thing; 

: : defined as well as other things) we say the attri- 
bute (that is, a defining mark) must exist only 

: ^:ii<all) the instances of the thing defined (and itf 
nothin! 



r — / » 



?■;:■ 



■ ■■; 

■1 



3 mIdhva logic 

What, then, is the purpose or end (prayojana) 
subserved by the knowledge of a defining mark ? ,| 
The purpose or end subserved by the knowledge i 
of a defining mark is the differentiation of -■ 
the thing defined from all other things of a 
homogeneous or heterogeneous nature as also the 
correct use of terms (without a too wide or too 
narrow meaning) . A thing is said to be homo- 
geneous (sajatlya) with the thing defined 
when it is specified by the next higher class that 
subsumes the defined thing under itself. (This 
means that the homogeneous is a species co- v 
ordinate with the thing defined and subsumed. | 
under the same immediately higher genus.) \| 
A thing is said to be heterogeneous (vijatiya) 
with the thing defined when it is not specified^ 
by the immediately higher genus that subsumes 
under itself the character of the thing defined.,! 
Thus in the definition of the * cow,* 'the essence J 
of being a cow ' or ' cow-ness ' constitutes th^f| 
character of the thing defined. The immediately | 
higher genus comprehending this character (ofy 
'cowness') is .' animality. ' Therefore the horse 
and other animals which are characterised by 
this generic character of animality are homo- 
geneous (sajathja) with the 'cow.' (Contrary- 
wise,) the jar and other things which are non*g 
characterised by this generic character (o& 
'animality') are heterogeneous (vijatiya) with 
the 'cow.' By 'an immediately higher genra^T 



-i*i 



i-^ 



PRAMA^ACANDRIKA. 9 

or ' next higher genus * is meant a genus which 
while not including any higher class inclusive of 
the thing defined is yet inclusive of the thing 
defined. Thus in the example of 'animality/ 
since the class of animals is inclusive of the class 
of cows without including the class of material 
objects which also includes the class of cows, the 
animal-class must be understood as the im- 
mediately higher genus in relation to the cow- 
class. These considerations (concerning the 
nature of the next higher genus) leave no room 
for the objection that all things being included 
under one all-inclusive class, viz., the class of 
knowables and the like, are all homogeneous with 
one another and that therefore there is no real 
heterogeneity anywhere. (Since all things come 
under a common all-inclusive class, viz., the 
class of knowables, they must all be said to be 
of the same class or genus, i.e., homogeneous. 
How then can you sensibly talk of the hetero- 
geneous and of one thing being heterogeneous 
with another? The answer to this objection is 
furnished by the definitions we have given above 
of the homogeneous and the heterogeneous as 
based on the concept of the next higher genus. 
When a thing is included under the next higher 
genus or class of the thing defined, it is said to 
be homogeneous with the thing defined. SVhen 
a thing is iiot so included, it is said to be 
heterogeneous.) In tins way in all other defini- 

2 



10 . MADHVA LOGIC J 

tions the homogeneous and the rest are to be .■ 
understood. 

(Having explained the nature of a valid 
logical definition, we shall now proceed to explain 
what constitutes the opposite, i.e., an invalid 
definition or non-definition.) 

An invalid definition or non-definition is 
the negation of a logically valid definition. 
Hence it is the negation of "that which, 
existing in every instance of the thing 
defined, is non-existent in things other than 
the instances of the thing defined." As a .'; 
negation, it is of the nature of a negation ; ; 
of a qualified thing. . A qualified negation ..;; 
or a negation negating a qualified thing may 
be of three kinds, viz., (a) a qualified nega- 
tion negating the thing qualified, (&) a'.| 
qualified negation negating the qualification ;| 
of the thing, (c) a qualified negation negating 
both the thing qualified and the quali- 
fication of it. (An invalid definition is a qualified 
negation, because it is the negation of a valid %t 
definition which consists of a substantive and an 
adjectival part, the substantive portion being 
' that which is non-existent in other things ' and 28 
the adjective qualifying it being ' while existing 'k 
in every instance of the thing defined.' Thus 
a non-definition, as being the negation of this 
substantive qualified by the adjectival portion, 
is a qualified negation.) Thus the non-definition 






fcRAMAtfACANDRIKA. 11 

"The cow is an animal possessing horns " is a 
qualified negation negating the substantive 
part of a valid logical definition. (It negates the 
condition that 'the defining mark must not 
exist in anything other than an instance of the 
thing defined.' ' Possession of horns ' is existent 
also in animals which are not cows.) Again the 
non-definition * The cow is an animal possessing 
mixed colour ' is a qualified negation negating the 
qualification (that characterises a valid defini- 
tion). (The qualification 'existing in every 
instance of the thing defined ' is negated in this 
case as every cow does not possess mixed colour.) 
Lastly, the non-definition ' The cow is an animal 
possessing undivided hoofs ' illustrates a qualified 
negation negating the substantive as well as 
the adjectival part of a valid definition. ('Posses- 
sion of undivided hoofs' is present in animals 
that are not cows and absent in cows. Thus it 
negates the substantive 'absence from other 
things ' and also the adjective ' existing in every 

case of the thing defined.') 

(Having explained the nature of a logical 
definition and its opposite, we shall now proceed 
to explain the nature of pariksa or examination.) 

Examination or sifting of evidence (pariksa) 
is mentally reflecting on the cogency or 
otherwise (of the evidence that has been 
adduced). Too wide use (ativyapU) consists in 
the use of a defining mark that exists in things 



■■■'.• 



v> 



12 madhVa LOGlO 

other than the thing defined. Too narrow use 
(avyapti) consists in the use of a defining mark 
that doe£ not exist in a part of the extent (i.e., 
in some instances) of the thing defined. Ab- 
surdity (asambhava) consists in the use of a 
property as a defining mark that does not exist 
in any instance of the thing defined. That 
which is defined by the defining mark is called 
the laksya or thing defined. 

(Let us now proceed to define the 
subject-matter of this work, viz., Pramana.) 
Pramana as such (i.e., pramana in general as 
distinguished from any particular kind of 
pramana) may therefore be first of all defined 
here. Pramana (we hold) is that which agrees, 
with the nature of the object (known). This 
means that the essence of pramana consists in | 
making the cognitum an object (of cognition) in 
the form in which it actually exists. There are M 
many things to be said here, but as this treatise 4S 
is meant for young learners and as (more) in- | 
telligent people may know all these from the 
work called the Paddhati, therefore they are not 
mentioned here.* The same observations hold 



* The Pramdnapaddhati observes that pramana is here so defined 

as to apply both to tbe cognitive process and the knowledge that results 

therefrom. The cognitive process conduces to the apprehension of the 

cognitum as it actually exists and is called Anupramapa. The resulting 

knowledge also apprehends the cognitum as it actually exists and is, 

called kevatopramana. 

{Pramdpapaddhati t Madhva ViWsa Edition* p. 



■'/}■ 



A! 



■Wk ■■■- 









1L^ V V 



also in respect of other matters that will come up 
later on (in this treatise). 

In the above definition of Pramana, since 
the property of apprehending the object is common 
to valid as well as doubtful and erroneous 
cognitions, the qualification ' in the form in 
which it actually exists* has been included. If 
we had defined Pramana merely as that which 
abides in the form in which it actually exists, 
then our definition would apply also to the 
cogniser and the cognitum (since these also 
abide in the form in which they actually exist), :., :: 
and thus will be too wide. Therefore we say : it 
must apprehend the cognitum as well (and not 
merely that it should abide in the form in which 
it actually exists) . Here ' apprehending the 
cognitum* means 'apprehending the cognitum! * x 
immediately as well as mediately* (through the ;■'..£■■+} 
help of a cognitive process). Hence our definition '* .;.;|j 
as applying also to the cognitive processes of ,j|| 
perception and the rest (as also to the knowledge v;J 

that results therefrom) cannot be said to be too .. : v 
narrow. Nor can this be said to be an illegiti- 
mate extension of the meaning of the term 
Pramana, for such extension is quite unexception- ■;\ 
able (inasmuch as the term Pramam is, as a 
matter of fact, used in both the above two senses 
of the cognitive processes and the resulting 
: knowledge)'. " " J* ■■' '' J 

The subject who cognises a valid cognition 



12 



MADHVA LOGIC 



■A 



is called the cogniser or knower. The object that 
is cognised by a valid cognition is called the 
cognitum or object known. Knowledge of the 
object as it actually exists is called valid knowledge 
or valid cbgnition. If valid knowledge were not ■ 
defined as a form of knowledge, our definition 
would be too wide as applying also to the 
processes which are only instrumental in the 
production of valid knowledge.* Similarly, if . 
valid knowledge were not defined as apprehension 
of the object as it actually exists, our definition "j 
would also be too wide as applying to doubtful 

is? 

cognitions and the rest. .^1 

What, then, is the essence of a doubtful;^! 

cognition {saw&aya) ? It may be said that it cannak|| 
be said to consist merely in an indefinite appre£!| 
hension for this amounts to a mutual dependence '::::{ 
(a circular definition). Thus (one may argue) io||j 
so far as a certain cognition is a definite apprehe«?J|| 
sion the definition of a doubtful cognition as mergg^ 
indefinite apprehension amounts to a circular^ 
definition in asmuch as a certain cognition is the 
other of a doubtful cognition and a doubtful cog- 



* ~*5 



* A distinction is drawn betweeu Pramd, valid knowledge, and 
Pramana, the instrument of valid knowledge. Pramana signifies both 
the source of the knowledge and the knowledge itself (as correct appre- 
hension of the object). But Pramd means the knowledge only and 
its instrumental means. Thas PramS must be distinguished from 
processes of intellection that bring about the result of valid knowli 
but Pramana may be used alike for the cognitive processes and 
knowledge that results therefrom. 




prama^acandrikI 

nitioii (defined as indefinite apprehension) is like- 
wise the other of a certain cognition. This 
argument, we hold, is not a sound one. An 
indefinite apprehension is in reality the correct 
definition of a doubtful cognition. There is no 
circle involved in this definition (as is contended 
by the opponent). For by the term 'indefinite 
apprehension ' is here meant a cognition that 
appears clothed (bathed) in the numerous 
mutually incompatible forms that manifest them- 
selves in (float on the surface of) one single thing. 
If we had defined doubtful cognition as that 
which is a cognition our definition would be too 

wide as applying also to the case of the (certain) 

cognition 'There is a jar here.' Therefore 
we say *it must be clothed in many forms.' 
Even so however our definition would be too 
wide as applying also to composite or collective 
cognitions such as the simultaneous cognition 
of a man and a post, or of a jar, a piece of cloth, 
a pillar and a pitcher, etc. To exclude such 
composite (certain) cognitions we say ' there must 
be one single thing' (in which the different 
forms are apprehended). But even then our 
definition remains too wide as applying to cog- 
nitions like ' This tree is of the Sim^upa species,' 
'The jar is a substance,' etc. (In these also 
there is cognition of different forms in a single 
thing.) Therefore (to exclude these), we say 'the 
different forms must be mutually incompatible. 1 



« 



16 MADHVA LOGIC 

But even so, our definition remains too wide 
as applying to erroneous cognitions like "This 
is silver/ (In the case of the cognition 
of silver in the locus of a mother of pearl, there 
are two incompatible forms, viz.* the form of , 
mother-of-pearl and the form of silver, and these 
forms refer to one single thing, viz., the mother- 
of-pearl, and yet the illusion of silver in the i 
mother-of-pearl is not a doubtful cognition.) J 
To exclude such erroneous cognitions we say (not | 
merely that there should be numerous incom- 
patible forms but also) that, - the numerous incom- 
patible forms should also manifest themselves^ 
as incompatible. 1 (In the case of the illusion*^ 
the form of silver manifests itself while that of 
mother-of-pearl remains non-manifest to the 
cogniser.) Thus (since in the doubtful cog] 
the different incompatible forms are held also tte 
present themselves as incompatible forms (refett|f 
ring to one single thing), our definition is noij- 
open to the aforesaid objection (of being too^ 

wide). - 

Some hold that this doubtful cognition 
arises, with the absence of its solvent as an 
auxiliary condition, from five different cau 
viz., (1) (cognition of) a common character, 

(2) (cognition of) an uncommon chara 

(3) (cognition of) contradictory characters (in 
and the same thing), (4) positive cognition 
certain objects) , and (5) non-cognition 



:■,. 



■M 






% 



PRAMAJjTACANDRIKA 17 

certain objects). A doubt arising from the 
perception of a common character is illustrated 
in the case of the perception of a certain tall 
stature which is common to a man and a post. 
The perception of this common character calls 
forth a simultaneous recollection of the two 
forms of 'man' and 'post' in the perceiver's 
mind as the result of which there arises in the 
latter a desire to ascertain the true nature (of the 
thing perceived, i. e., a desire to ascertain 
whether the object perceived is 'a man* or 'a 
post.') In the absence, however, of perception 
of the crucial test, viz., the curved hollow which 
is peculiar to the trunk of a tree or the possession 
of a head, hands, etc., which is peculiar to a man, 
there arises a doubt in the form of a mental 
oscillation (between the two alternatives in the 
form) ' Is that a man ? ' ' Or, Is that a post?.', ; A 
doubt arising from the cognition of an uncom- 
mon character is illustrated in the following case. 
The cognition that sound is a quality that 
belongs exclusively to Ether (Ikaia) awakens 
a doubt, in the absence of a perception of the 
solvent, as to whether it is an eternal or a non- 
eternal quality. A doubt arising from the clash 
of contradictory views is illustrated in the fofe;, 
lowing case.. The man who discovers that the 
.yaise§ikas teach that the sensibilities are consti- 
■/•*gted by the.; elements t$: that the 8aiik%* 
■ -teaches that they are aofc -and at the :■&&&&»» 



.,*> 



18 MADHVA LOGIC 



# 



cannot find the means of deciding between the 
rival views is thrown into doubt as to whether the 
sensibilities are constituted by the elements or 
not. A doubt arising from a positive cognition 
is illustrated in the case of a man who first 
discovers the underground water in the act of 
sinking a well. The discovery of the water 
throws him into a speculative doubt (as to the 
real source of the water), and he thus enquires, 
for want of a solvent, as follows : 'Has the action 
of digging only made manifest the water which 
has been existent all along but remained non- 
manifest? Or, has it made the non-existent 
water start into existence? The following, 
lastly, illustrates the case of a doubt arising from 
non-apprehension. The man who learns from 
hearsay that there lives a ghost in the banyan 
tree yonder and yet finds none when he comes If? 
near the tree is thrown into a mental uncertainty 
as he does not cognise the solvent. He thus 
enquires : ' Is the demon not perceived because :^ 
of its power of making itself invisible? Or, is it 
unperceived because it does not exist ? ' * jl 

Others hold that positive cognition and non- ■ 
apprehension (as causes of doubt) being only'J 
modalities of the 'common character' (as a 
cause of doubt), doubtful cognition must be 
said to have three causes only (and not five 
as stated above). How is- -'positive- cognition?: 
to be regarded as a modality of the 'common! 



■ # m g 

1 



■ft! 

'■■- 



% 



PRAMAVACANDRIKA 19 

character* that is supposed to be a cause of doubt? 
In this way. There is positive cognition 
of a jar that exists in a dark place when 
a lamp is lighted and the surrounding darkness 
is dispelled thereby. There is also positive 
cognition of a jar that did not exist previously 
till the potter has operated on the lump of clay 
and brought a jar into being. (The positive 
cognition is thus a character that is common to 
an existent and a non-existent thing and thus 
raises doubt as to the existence or non-existence of 
the object in the mind of the cogniser). How 
is non-apprehension a modality of the 'common 
character?' In this way. There is non-appre- 
hension of the existent such as the non-perception 
of God as well as of the non-existent such as the 
non -perception of the hair's horn. (Thus non- 
perception as appertaining alike to the existent 
and the non-existent raises doubt as to the 
existence or the opposite of the object noa- 
perccived.) 

But the true view is that the so-called 'un- 
common character' as well as 'the clash of 
contradictory views * being really modalities 
of the 'common character,' there is only one 
cause of doubtful cognitions, viz., the cognition 
of a common character.' The way in which these 
(ti2., 'the uncommon character,' 'the clash of 
doctrines,' etc.) are to be regarded as comprised 
in the ' common character * should be understood 



20 



MADHVA LOGIC 



* • 



in the manner they are shown to be so comprised 
in the work called the 'Paddhati.' 

(Having explained the nature of doubt we 
now proceed to explain the nature of erroneous 

cognition.) 

An error (viparyaya) is a cognition con- 
sisting in the conscious certitude that a thing 
exists just where as a matter of fact it does 
not exist. If we define an error simply as a 
cognition, our definition will apply also to 
doubtful cognitions (which are also cognitions 
and thus will be too wide* Hence we define* 
error as a cognition which amounts to a certain^ 
knowledge or conviction. This excludes the| 
cases of doubtful and uncertain cognitions. Bti| 
since valid cognition is also as much self-eonfidenl- 
as invalid cognition or error, we define error as i 
cognition that apprehends a thing where 
reality the thing does not exist. This di 
tinguishes an error or invalid cognition f 
valid cognition and thus our definition is fi 
too wide. But even thus our definition fails 
exclude the cases of doubtful cognitions, 
doubtful cognition (though lacking in certitu 
or decisiveness) also apprehends a thing where 
does not exist. Hence we say, an error is;-| 
certain cognition. Even thus however our de 
tion remains faulty as applying to the case 
valid cognitions as well, e.g., the cogni 
'the tree is in contact with the 



"3 







pramAsacandrikI 21 

The contact does not exist in all parts 
of the tree. (Therefore contact is asserted in 
respect of an object which is devoid of contact 
in some of its parts). Hence we insist on the 
word just in our definition, i.e., we say an error 
cognises a thing just where the thing does not 
exist. Such errors arise from faulty perceptions, 
fallacious reasonings and defects of verbal com- 
munications. The illusion of silver in the locus 
of a mother-of-pearl is an illustration of error 
arising from faulty perception. An error of 
reasoning is illustrated in the case of the man 
who under the influence of blinding dust imagines 
he perceives smoke and on the basis of the 
illusory smoke infers the existence of fire in a , 
place where fire does not exist. Similarly, 
when on the strength of the lying report of an 
untrustworthy man one believes that there are , 
five different fruits lying on the banks of *■_..,: 
neighbouring river, we have a case of an errO*^ 
arising from a faulty verbal communication. :-;.;.-,: 
An objection however may be raised here), .^ 
We have defined Pramana as consisting in making f 
the object of cognition to be cognised in the 
form in which it exists (actually). Butthe defini- 
tion may be objected to as being too wide applying 
as it does to the case of 'memory' also (*Hjg$ 
•is not usually recognised as a Pramana)- Our 
reply is : this is not so, for scripture testifies to 
jgftf^flf that 'men^,f ; >rception,* : ;iaF^^r-; 



22 mIdhva logic 



*._« 



"3 



*i 



and * inference ' are to be regarded as the 1 
pramanas or valid sources of knowledge in regard 
to such things as (dharma) merit and the like, 
by all those who desire liberation. Thus we 
have the testimony of scripture showing that 
memory is a form of valid knowing. 

Some philosophers define pramana as the 
karana or instrumental cause of prama or valid 
cognition. An instrument as such (according to 
them) is not a pramana, otherwise any instrument 
such as an axe would rank as pramana. Hence 
the definition of pramana as an instrument of 
valid cognition (and not as a mere instrument). 
Similarly the epithet ' valid * is also necessary as >! 
without it the definition would apply to non- | 
valid and erroneous cognition and thus be 
too wide. Lastly, the word instrument is also! 
necessary as without it the definition would I 
tantamount to an absurdity and also be tofr| 
wide as applying to the consequence or result J 
that follows from the instrumentality of valid 
knowing. 

We however do not accept the above view as^| 
we consider the definition too narrow as not-| 
applying to the result of valid knowing. (Our*' 
view is that the word pramana signifies the 
knowing act as well as the result of knowledge 
that arises therefrom.) 

Others define pramana as that which is; 
pervaded by prama or valid knowledge. 



PRAMAtfACANDRIKl &3 

This also is not a tenable position. Every 
knowable object is validly cognised by the Lord. 
Hence every knowable such as the jar and the 
like is pervaded by the Lord's valid knowledge. 
Thus every knowable answers to the above defini- 
tion of pramana or valid knowing as that which 
is pervaded by valid knowledge. Thus the defini- 
tion is too wide as applying to knowables (and 
not merely to knowing acts). 

With a view to escape from the above 
difficulty, others modify the above definition as 
follows : — Pramana is that which being either a 
substrate or an instrument is at the same time 
pervaded by valid knowledge. 

Even thus however the definition is not fault- 
less. The mention of the word 'substrate' in 
the definition is without rhyme or reason Even 
granting that the Lord is regarded as a standard 
of validity, it cannot be said that this in itself 
is a sufficient reason for introducing the word 
1 substrate ' in the definition. For the word 
pramana is derived by means of the suffix lyut, 
and, according to the rules of grammar, the suffix 
lyut applies only to the instrumental, the locative 
and the nominative absolute. There is no rule 
for its application to a nominative as such, i.e. 
(as in the present case), to the agent, nominative 
or subject of valid knowing. (The Lord is 
regarded as the standard of valid knowing only 
as the absolute knower, ie., as the agent or 



-:*\ 



24 



MADHVA LOGIC 



H< 



subject of absolute knowledge and not as its^ 
substrate or instrument.) 

It may be argued that even though the 
as knower is the subject of knowledge, yet 
also is the substrate or locus of such knowledge, 
and thus may very well be the meaning of the 
word pramana. But even this argument does not 
bear examination. The Lord as knower is aO^g 
agent of the knowing act and not its substrate Cji 
locus in the strict sense. For what is a locus 
adhikarana? A locus is that which is the adh 
or container of the agent acting or the obj 
acted on and is at the same time the a&raya-a 
substrate of the action itself. (The Lord c 
be the substrate of the knowing act of w 
He is the subject.) 

Others (the Prabhakaras) define PramanI f 
anubhuti, i.e., as the apprehension of a.-fi 
By anubhuti they mean cognition other than n 
collection or memory. According to . t 
anubhuti cannot be defined simply as ' other 
recollection/ for in this case the definition 
apply to objects of cognition like the jar and 
rest (which are other than recollection). \ 
ean it be defined simply as e cognition/ for 
this case the definition will apply to ' recollection^ 
(which is not an independent source of knowledge 

according to Prabhakaras). _ : ,.,V.: 

v But the Prabhakara definition of Pramapft H 
open to the following objections,; .yte^bg$ 




■im 



.i-'-S 



. ".'» 



^£i&H 



' ' \ 



PRAMi^ACANDRIKA 25 

place, it is too wide as applying to doubtful 
cognitions (which are also forms of apprehension 
or anubhuti other than recollection). Secondly 
it is also too narrow as not applying to memory 
(smrti) and the social codes derived from the 
Vedas. (Smrti means recollection as well as the 
social codes based on the Vedas and their teach- 
ings. The latter are analogous to recollection 
which is based on an original primary presenta- 
tion. The Madhvas accept smrti as pramana in 

both these senses.). - 

(This closes our discussion of the definition of 
Pramaqa. We now proceed to discuss its different 

varieties.)! - - - '-■ ■"«■' 
Pramana is of two kinds, viz., (1) Kevda? 
pramana, i.e., self-contained, absolute knowing, 
and (2) Anupramdna, i.e.,. valid knowing 
as the instrumental cause of self-contained, 
absolute knowing. This enumeration is baaed! 
on the order of importance. (Kevalapramafa 
being of superior importance is first mea*>: 
tioned.) ". ,..;.^,; 

- ** 

Kevalapramam means knowledge that agrees 
with the nature of the object known. The words 
'■ agrees with the nature of the object ' dispose 
of uncertain and doubtful cognitions, while the 
word 'knowledge' disposes of percerang (and 
other intervening processes). (Keratapraro^ii*^ 
the resulting knowledge as distinguished from the 
processes leading thereto.) ■ <■'-..■•■&£$§$$&"■ 

"4 ' ■ ' 

4 



26 MADHVA LOGIC 

There are four kinds of Kevalapramana (i.e.> 
four kinds of self-sufficient, self-contained 
knowledge) : — (1)* the knowledge of the Lord or 
Ihara, (2) the knowledge of the Lord's Consort, 
Atfcj Laksml, (3) the knowledge of the Sage or 
Yogin A (4) the knowledge of the Non-Sage or 
Ayogin. 

The Lord's knowledge is the knowledge that 
rests on, i.e., presupposes, itself only. The fact 
of its l depending on itself only ' distinguishes the 
Lord's knowledge from that of the Lord's Consort. 
(The Consort's knowledge, while depending on 
itself, also depends on the Lord's knowledge.) 
The fact of its being i knowledge ' distinguishes 
it from the Lord Himself whose knowledge it is. 
(This is aimed at the Shankarite theory according 
to which Brahman is nothing but pure self- 
revealing Intelligence. The Madhvas distinguish 
between the Lord Himself and the knowledge 
which the Lord has of Himself and all other 
things.) Or, we may say, the Lord's knowledge is 
knowledge that embraces all that appertains either 
to the Lord Himself or to that which is other 
than the Lord. The Lord's knowledge cannot be 
defined simply as knowledge, for in this case the :|| 
definition will be too wide as applying to the J 
Yogin's knowledge as well (which is alsp : .J§ 
knowledge of a sort). To exclude the latter, the;? 
definition stresses the words ' that embraces attgj 
etc.' (The Yogin's knowledge is not all-embracing 



•*» 






prama#ac"andri£a 2? 

as is the Lord's). Further, the word ' knowledge ' : 
prevents a too wide application of the definition 
to the perception of the Lord. The Lord's 
knowledge is invariably in agreement with the 
nature of the object known, constitutes the 
essence or svarupa of the Lord, is without 
beginning and without end. 

The Consort's knowledge is knowledge that 
depends on, i.e., presupposes, the Lord's knowledge 
only. If the Consort's knowledge had been 
defined simply as ' knowledge,* the definition would 
have been too wide and applicable to the Lord's 
knowledge as well. To exclude the latter, the 
words * depending on the Lord's knowledge* have 

been added. Since dependence implies a distinc- 
tion (between the dependent and that on which 
it depends), the possibility of confusion (between 
the Consort's knowledge and the Lord's knowledge) 
is precluded. But mere dependence on the Lord's 
knowledge does not fully define the Consort's 
knowledge. The knowledge of Brahma and 
others is also characterised by this dependence 
on the Lord's knowledge. To preclude such 
extension of the definition (to the knowledge of 
Brahma and others), the word 'only* has been 
added. (The Consort's knowledge depends on the 
Lord's knowledge only, but the knowledge of 
Brahma and others depends both on the Lord's 
knowledge and the Consort's knowledge.) Further,; 
the word c knowledge r in the definition serves to 



2& MADHVA LOGIC 

distinguish the Consort's knowledge from the J 
Consort herself. Or, we may say, the Consort's 
knowledge is the non-reflective knowledge of all 
objects other than the Lord Himself. Here the '§ 
word * knowledge' by itself fails to distinguish 
the Consort's knowledge from knowledge like - 
that of ourselves. Hence to prevent such too 
wide application, the words ( of all objects ' have . ^ 
been added. Even then the definition has a too, -1 
wide application to the Rju login's knowledge. 
(The $ju Yog in also has a reflective knowledge, 
of all objects). Hence the word 'non-reflective.*^ 
The Rju-Yogin has only a reflective knowledge of 
objects. Again to say that 'the Consort's 
knowledge is the non-reflective knowledge of all 
objects ' does not distinguish it from the Lord's :i 
knowledge (and thus the definition as so worded 
remains too wide). Heoce the further qualifier 
tion 'excepting the Lord Himself.' But the 
Words * non-reflective knowledge of all object£| 
and no 3uch knowledge of the Lord Himself 
would be absurd and self -confuting. Henflg 
the words 'other than 5 {%. e., non-reflecti 
knowledge of all things other than the 
Himself). Further, the word r knowledge * iij| 
the definition distinguishes it from the Consort* 
perception (t. e.» the process of percei 
which leads to A or results in, knowl 
The Consort's knowledge is also inv 
in agreement with reality^ is the esse 



■ ■ .. 




** J . 



PRAMAtfACANDRIKl 29 

of the Consort herself and is beginningless and 

eternal. 

The Yogin' s knowledge is the knowledge that 
has attained to special perfection or excellence 
through the power born of the practice of yoga 
or mental concentration. It is of three kinds, 
viz., (1) the Rju Yogin's knowledge, (2) the 
Tattvika Yogin's knowledge, (3) the Atattvika 

Yogin's knowledge. 

By Rju Yogin is meant a jiva or individual 
soul who is capable of the spiritual excellence of 
Brahman. The Rju Yogin's knowledge is the 
reflective knowledge of all objects other than the 
Lord Himself. As the mere words 'the Rju 
Yogin s knowledge is knowledge ' will not prevent, 
a too wide application of the definition to our; 
knowledge as well, the words * of all objects * h$v 
"been added. As even theo them. is a 

^application to the Lord's knowledge, 
* reflective * has been incorporated. As th 
the definition entails an absurdity, the 
being a reflective knowledge of all 
and yet not a knowledge of the Lord 
the words 'other than the Lord Himself ' BS*R=^ 
been added. This knowledge is of two kinds &^*$j& 
(o) knowledge which is the essence or nature of '^M& 
the , Yogin himself, and (&) knowledge which is 
only a mental state of the Yogin. Of these* 
knowledge constituting the Yogin's essence jft! 

^begraningless and etaajfeJifcUe knowledge ]|I» 










fe:* 



>:**■*'■■ y *" m ■'**■ 



*.. 



m 



30 MADHVA LOGIC 

Yogin's mental state is beginningless only as 
being comprised in a (beginningless) flow 
stream (of states). Both these however are inH 
variably in agreement with the nature of thej 

objects (known). 

The Tattvika Yogins are the supernal beings 
(with godly qualities) other than the Rju Yogins 
and full of the conceit of true knowledge of 
reality. Merely saying that Y the Tdttvika$j> 
are the gods with self-conscious knowledge of 
reality ' would have involved a too wide applica- 
tion to the Rju Yogins (who also have sdfH 
conscious knowledge of reality). Hence the 
words 'other than the Rju Yogins. 9 Merely 
saying again that * the Tattvikas are other tharf 
the Rju Yogins would have involved a- 
wide application to the gods or spirits who are 
non-Tattvikas. Hence the words 'with self 
conscious knowledge of reality.' Since there 
also ungodly beings (other than Rju Yogins) wh#j 
also have self-conscious knowledge of reality^ 
therefore the words ' with godly qualities * have 
been added. The Tattvika Yogin's knowledge $ 
that which being beginningless does not, even 
by way of reflection, embrace all things other 
than the Lord. Merely saying that ' the Tdttvi 
Yogin's knowledge is knowledge ' would ha 
entailed a too wide application to the Lord' 
knowledge. Hence the words c does not embra 
all things.' Even then there would have been 



yfi.i 



% 



PRAMA^ACANDRIKA 31 

too wide application to the Consort's knowledge. 
The Consort's knowledge is non-all-embracing in 
so far as it does not extend to the Lord Himself. 
Hence the words ' other than the Lord.' Even 
then, there would have been a too wide application 
to the Rju Yogin's knowledge, for the Rju Yogin's 
knowledge does not embrace all things other than 
the Lord in the absence of reflection. Hence 
the words 'even by way of reflection/ Even 
then, however,, the definition would have a too 
wide application to the non-Tattvika Yogin's 
knowledge. Hence the words 'being beginning- 
less/ It also is of two kinds, viz., (a) knowledge 
which constitutes the svarupa or essence of the 
Tattvika Yogin, and (b) knowledge which is 
external (i.e., relates to external objects). - Of 
these, 'essential 5 knowledge is in agreement with 
reality, but * external ' knowledge is occasionally 
false, i.e., not in agreement with the nature of 
things. ... 

The non-Tattvikas or 'Atdttvikas are the Gods 
and Sages practising Yoga who are other than the 
Rju and the Tattvika Yogin$. The non-Tattvika 
Yogin's knowledge is that which, having a 
beginning in time, is characterised by slight or 
partial ignorance in respect of objects other than 
the Lord. Merely saying that the non-Tattvika 
Yogin's knowledge is knowledge would have 
entailed a too wide application to the Lord's 
irT^TxriafW rrWAfnrp .thii words * characterised 



> 







32 MADHVA LOGIC 



by ignorance' have been incorporated. Even! 
then there would have been a too wide applicant 
to the non- Yogin's knowledge. Hence the word 
' slight or partial/ Even then the definition would| 
have entailed an absurdity, for the non-TattmW4 t t 
knowledge in respect of the Lord is tainted by 
immense (and not slight) ignorance. Hence the;-* 
Words ' other than the Lord/ Even then there 
would have been a too wide application to the 
Tattvika Yogin's knowledge. Hence the words 
'having a beginning in time/ This also is 
two kinds, viz., essential knowledge, and exl 
knowledge. The rules as to their truth or untrutl 
are the same as in the previous case. The begin-: 
ninglessness and the beginning-in4ime of 
Tattvika and the wm-Tattvika Yogin's knowli 
respectively should be understood in the mann< 
explained in the f Paddhati/ 

The non-Yogins or Ayogins are the individi 
souls other than the Yogins or sages. The wo] 
* Jivas or individual souls ? differentiates 
Ayogins from the Lord and the Lord's C< 
and the words 'other than the Yogins* 
tinguish the Ayogins from the Yogins. 
■. The Ayogin's knowledge is knowledge chi 
tensed by immense ignorance in regard to obj< 
other than the Lord. Merely saying that 
Ayogin's knowledge is knowledge chai 
by immense ignorance' would have entailed 
too wide application to the Yarn's 



T"«. 



*tfCi 



-#** 




PRAMA^ACANDRIKA 33 

also. The Yogin's knowledge is also accompanied 
by immense ignorance, viz., in regard to the 
Lord. Hence the words 'other than the Lord/ 
The Ayogin's knowledge is also of two kinds as 
in the previous cases. Besides, it is also 
generated in time and perishable in time. This 
generation or cessation means generation or 
cessation with respect to the manifestation of the 
svarupa or essence. The svarUpa or essence here 
means the svarupa or essence of the knowing as 
a cognitive process or state. 

The Ayogins or non-Yogins are also of three 
kinds : (1) those that are fit for liberation, (2) 
those that are perpetual participators in (the 
storm and stress of) life, (3) those that are fit 
only to live the stupefied life of inertia or Tamas. 
Of these, ' essential ' knowledge in the case of 
' those fit to be liberated ' is in agreement with 
the nature of reality, while the same in * the 
perpetual participators in life* is of a mixed 
character (partly true and partly false). Of 
others, however, such knowledge is false as being 
in non-agreement with reality- As regards 
' external ' knowledge, it is both (true and false, 
».e., in some cases true and in other cases false) 
in all the three kinds of the non-Yogins.. 

The Vaisesikas accept sense-perception, ^ 
inference from a mark, memory and the intuitions 
of the Sages as the four kinds of valid evidene&o: 
Thio ah* Voieofiiw via™} hnwe.ver is untenable 



'-■*ii 



34 MADHVA LOGIC 

> 

as this enumeration does not include the Lord's 
knowledge which is timeless and eternal as also 
knowledge derived from authoritative communica- 
tion (Agama). Further, recollection being the 
effect of the action of the mind which is a 
sense-organ, and the intuitions of sages being 
only a species of Yogik knowledge, and Yogik 
knowledge being itself a variety of sense-knowledge 
aided by the power of Yoga (according to their 
own admission), there is no reason for a separate 
enumeration of memory or recollection and of. 
the intuitions of sages as independent sources of; 

knowledge. 

[Having explained the nature of direct self^ 

contained knowledge (kevalapramaw), we sh 
.now discuss the nature of pramfma as Ann* 
pramdiia or mediating processes.] 

Anupramana is the means or instrumental can 
of valid knowledge. Merely saying * Anuprama 
is knowledge ' would entail a too wide applicati 
to knowledge itself (which is the result or effe 
of Anupramana) and to uncertain and doubtf 
cognition (which also is a species of knowledge 
though not valid knowledge). Again ■, merel; 
saying 'Anupramana is an instrument or effec- 
tuating means ' will entail a too wide applicati 
to the axe and other like instruments. Ag 
merely saying 'Anupramana is valid knowled 
will entail a too wide application to Kevalt 
pramana (which is direct, self-contained v 



■%i 



m 



* 







PHAMA^ACANbRlKA \> V^5-^" - W 

knowledge). Simply saying again that l Anu- 
pramafta is the instrument of that which is valid ' 
will entail a too wide application to the instru- 
ment of perception (which also is valid). Like- 
wise saying merely that 'Anupramaiia is the 
means to knowledge or cognition ' will entail a 
too wide application to that which is a means to 
doubtful cognition, etc. Lastly saying that 'Anu- 
pramana is the cause of valid cognition ' will 
entail a too wide application to the knower. 
Thus our definition of Anupramiina is proved to 
be necessary in all the points. 

(What, then is a sadhana, instrumental cause 
or means?) A Sadhana or instrument is that 
which being absent, the effect does not arise, even 
though other conditions like the knower, etc., are 
present, and which being present unobstructed, 
the effect necessarily arises. E.g., the axe in the 
process of striking (the tree to be felled) . Hence 
there is no too wide application to any and 
every concomitant condition, e.g., no too wide 
application to cases of erroneously cognised 
marks or signs. Where error is involved, the 
presence of defects of sensibilities, etc., is the bar 
(to the cognition of the really effective means). 

(The sadhana is thus the cause par excellence, 
i.e., the most effective of the causal conditions. 
And this brings us to the question of the. nature 
of the cause.) ..." 

The cause may be defined as the unconditional, 




36 MADHVA LOGIC 

invariable antecedent of the effect. And t 
effect may be defined as that which is nega 
by the negation * consisting in antecedent! 
non-existence. (This means that the effect 
is that which does not exist before it i 
caused to be.) The cause again is of two kinds/ 
viz.. the material cause and the instrumental 
cause. The cause which suffers transformation 
(into the effect) is the material cause, for 
example, Prakrti or primal matter as the cause 
the universe, the lump of clay as the cause of t 
jar. The cause which produces the effect witho 
being itself transformed thereinto is the inst 
mental cause, for example, the unseen m 
forces (Adrsta) as the cause of the universe, t. 
potter's stick as the cause of the jar. Hence 
follows that among the assemblage of caus; 
conditions that which is the cause par excellen&jjp 
(i.e., most effective) is the sadhana, means -A 
instrument. '^ 

. Anupramaqa is of three kinds, viz., percepti 
inference and authoritative communication. (' 
these) perception is the means to the appreh 
of that which is comparatively proximate, is 
mediated and present here and now. H 
perception is limited in range, being restricted 
a small number of objects (i.e., objects whic| 
are near and present and not separated by w 
barrier). Inference however is a means i& 
knowledge of the remote, the mediated 







■ L ■, 



&"■■ 



PRAMAtfACANDRIKA 37 

the past and the future. Lastly, Agama or 
authoritative communication is an independent 
source of the knowledge of all sorts of objects 
of which the number is endless. The above 
enumerative statement is based on the order of 
the kind and number of objects made known 
(respectively by the three kinds of knowing, viz. 9 
perception, inference and authority). There being 
three kinds of Anupramdna or effective means to 
valid cognition, the cognition resulting therefrom 
is also of three kinds, viz., perceptual, inferential 
and authoritative knowledge. Of these, percep- , 
tual knowledge is the cognition that is produced 
by the process of perceiving. This (cognition) is 
what is meant by immediate knowledge, direct . 
knowledge or witnessing knowledge (saksatkara) . 
Similarly, the knowledge reached through in- 
ference is called inferential or mediate knowledge. 
Lastly, the knowledge derived from authoritati^.^ 
communication is called authoritative knowledge 

or revealed knowledge. 

(What, then, is perception as a source rf-^ 
knowledge?) Perception is the process of *|| 
sense-organ that is free from defects. (In other^S 
words, perception is the stimulation, by the^ 
object, of an organ of sense not subject to anjf ;J> 
sensory defects.) Here the word 'sense-organ' 
prevents a too wide application to inference -iriti^ 

the rest. -'■ - ■ - '■ V •-*"'? ;W'w% 

Rnt it mav be said, perception is a species o 



:i! 



ct 



38 MADHVA LOGIC 

an instrumental cause, and an instrumental cause 
is possible only through an intervening action or 
operation. For example, the instrument of the 
act of cutting is the axe, and the axe is an instru- ,^ 
mental cause of the cutting or felling of the tree 
through the intervening operation of coming into 
contact with the tree. The intervening operation 
is that which being effected by the instrumental 
cause serves to effect that which results from 
the action of the instrumental cause, e.g., the 
contact with the tree which is effected by the axe. 
(What, then, is the intervening action in the 
case of perception as an instrumental cause or 
agency.') 

We grant the force of the question which is 
thus raised. And our answer is this. The sense- 
organ is the instrument, and the contact of the 
sense-organ with the object (perceived) is the 
intervening operation (through which the sense-; ^| 
organ produces its effect as an instrumental cause) 
The consequence or effect which results from 'i 
the action of the sense-organ as an instrument 
is direct or immediate knowledge (saksatkara) M 
Here the process or operation (i.e., the perceptive^ 
operation) is described as the operation of the| 
eye (i.e., of the sense-organ concerned) with 
a view to stress the fact that the organ (a*J 
the seat of the operation) is primary while the J 
operation inhering therein is secondary. Anjll 
further the organs are said to be free froflb 



PRAMAJJACANDRIKA 39 

defects and to be in contact with their respective 
objects with a view to ensure the truth or 
validity of the knowledge resulting therefrom. 
Hence there is no discrepancy in our definition. 

Perception is of seven kinds, viz., the six 
different kinds of perception consisting of the 
operations of the senses and the perception of the 
sdksi or witnessing consciousness. Of these, the 
perception of the witnessing consciousness is 
perception consisting in the operation of the 
Witnessing Intelligence as organ or instrument. 
The objects of such immediate knowledge or 
presentation are : the essence of the Self or 
Atman as well as the properties thereof, the 
nescience underlying absence or privation, the 
mind, the functions of the mind such as know- 
ledge, pleasure and the rest, time, Aka$a in its 
original unmodified condition, etc. It also 
reveals its own nature. 

(Sensuous perception as arising from the 
operation of the six different organs presupposes 
the six organs of sense.) The six sense-organs 
are the olfactory sense, the gustatory sense, the 
visual sense, the tactual sense, the auditory sense 
and the mind. Of these, the objects of the 
olfactory sense are odour and the different kinds of 
fragrance which are the specific modes of odour; 
the objects of the gustatory sense are tastes and 
its specific forms ; the objects of the visual sense 
and touch are substances having magnitude and 



40 "*' MADHVA LOGIC 



m 



perceptible (generated) colour and form, certaift^ 
qualities such as number and the rest, the 
different kinds of motion, and the generic;J 
characters. The feel of air is also an object of 
touch. Air itself is (not directly perceived by § 
touch, but only) inferred from its feel (which is % 
revealed to touch). (The inference is as follows.) ;: 
The wind that blows is felt as being neither hot _f_ 
nor cold. Since the feel is a quality like colour 
and cannot go wandering, there must be some sub- 
stance in which the feeling in question inheres or 
abides. What, then, is the substance which is the| 
substrate of the feeling in question ? It cannot 
be earth, for earth, though characterised by per-3 

ceptible touch, is also characterised by perceptibte| 
form and colour, whereas the feeling which i 
experienced (in the case of the blowing wind) 
evidently has no substrate of a perceptible fo 
and colour. Nor can the substrate in question b 
either water or fire, for the feel which it indu 
is not experienced as cold (as in the case 
water) or hot (as in the case of fire). Nor again 
can it be the four ubiquitous substances si 
they are all devoid of the quality of such feeling. 
The assumption of tactual properties in the 
quitous substances would entail a perception 
touch everywhere and at all times. Nor 
can the mind be the substrate in question, 
the mind is atomic or infinitesimal and the 
of the infinitesimal or atomic is impe 




PBAMA^fACANDRlKl Vj* \ 41 

V ks ^ 

i.e., beyond sense-perception. Hence we conw*- - • v 

that which constitutes the substrate of the quail 
that is felt by touch in the case in question is 
the (specific) substance we call air. 

But it may be said air is perceptible (and not 
inferred as above shown), because it is the 
substrate of a perceptible touch just as is the 
jar. This objection is not tenable, for air is the 
- substrate of perceptible touch only because of an 
adventitious condition, viz., its association with 
an object of perceptible form and colour. (An 
adventitious condition is anything that is in- 
variably correlated with the probandum but is } 
not an invariable correlate of the probans.) In ■■■ Q 
the case in question, the condition is an in- .- ■& 
variable correlate of the probandum as determined :% 
by the property of the subject in which it , : (^ 
is inferred. (The subject of the inference is |§ 
: air which is an external substance and the pro^/j|| 
bandum is perceptibility) . That the adventitious^ 
condition is perceptible colour and form is proved ,;/^| 
by the invariable correlation of external sob^gg 
stances that are perceptible and the presenpgj 
of perceptible colour and form together .*&*$$ 
the absence of any such correlation between tbe;|;g| 

■ ground of the inference, viz, ' being the BpbBfe^g| 
of perceptible touch ' and the adventitious condprf^ 

, tion, viz., the 'presence of perceptible colour^;;, J 

form.' Thus we find that whatever is an external 
■y Substance and is gerceived is also char^erised v;- 

■ .-"■ 6 



42 MiDHVA LOGIC 

by perceptible colour and form, but we cannot 
say that whatever is a substrate of a perceptible 
touch has also perceptible colour and form, 
(Hence being the substrate of a perceptible touch 
is a valid ground for perceptibility only on the 
condition that the substrate has perceptible colour 
and form and not otherwise. In other words, the 
ground is a ground only under conditions and 
not unconditionally and therfore the inference in 
question is not flawless.) Hence though you 
affirm the presence of the ground (viz., being 
the substrate of a perceptible touch), in the subject 
of the inference (viz., air), yet perceptible form and 
colour which always accompany the probandum^fj 
i.e., perceptibility, is no invariable correlate of J 
the ground (and so the ground fails to prove ) 
the presence of the probandim being shown-l 
to be no invariable correlate of an invariable . 

«** 

correlate of the probandum.) Hence it follows^ 
that air is inferred from its special touch (and 
not perceived as contended). 

The objects perceived by the auditory sense | 
are sounds and their varieties in the form of 
the alphabetical or verbal sounds. 

Inadvertence of the mind (partial or complete))! 
colour-blindness, jaundice, etc., are the defected 
of the five sensibilities. ,. /j 

The objects (of the five different senses) arfrl 
also objects of the mind (the sixth sense) and? 
the mind makes them its objects by presiding 



■ ■ j 
"A 



PRAMAtfACANDBIKi 43 

over and guiding and directing the operations of 
the five external senses. 

But the mind also perceives past events and 
in such perception it does not require the aid 
of the external senses. The result of such per- 
ception (of the past independently of the external 
senses) is memory or recollection. Memory is 
thus said to be an effect of internal perception 
(by the mind as the sixth sense). The contact 
of sense and object in this case (i.e., in the case 
of a direct perception of the past by means of 
the mind as the sixth sense) is furnished by 
what we call the Samshara, trace or disposition 
left behind by the past experience. (The mind 
as the sixth sense has a direct vision of the past 
and what we call the disposition or trace of the 
past experience is nothing but the contact of the 
past with the present, or as Bergson would say 
perhaps, the insertion or prolongation of the 
past into the present). The process (of the 
mind in recollection) is thus analogous to that 
of the specially gifted senses of the yogis which 
possess extraordinary supernal powers due to 
the practice of yogik concentration (and thereby 
cross the gulf between the past and the present). 

The defects of the mind (which vitiate the 
mental or internal perceptions) are desires, 

predispositions, etc. ,- 

There are also defects of the objects perceived 
(which interfere with their correct perception) and 



44 - MABHVA LOGIC 



■# 



■■£ 



these are long intervals (of time or space), closed 
proximity (in time or space), subtile or potentiaJJ 
condition of the objects, intervening barriers : 
(media) separating the objects from the perceiver,4 
non-manifestation of the objects (e.g., of the stars | 
in daylight), intermixture with objects of a like|g 
or similar nature, etc. : /ft§ 

These defects being present, in some cases the^| 
cognition itself is not generated and in some cases n 
doubt or uncertainty arises (as to the evidence ofc| 
; the cognition that is generated). - 

In the case of cognition due to the operation 
the senses, the cause consists of the contacts of the 
four beginning with the self. Thus the self mu 
come into contact with the mind, the mind wi 
the sensibilities, the sensibilities with the objects; 
The sensibilities have no immediate intuition of 
v objects at a distance and must actually dart fo 
to the place of the objects and come into contact 
with them in order to reveal them. The se 
same contacts which enable the sensibilities 
reveal their respective objects are also the imine* 
diate cause of the perception of their respecti^ 
absence. No intervening relations mediate 
tween the contacts and the absence in the case 
perception of absence (as Naiyayikas say). 

One school of philosophers (the Naiyayika 
": holds that the contact which brings on cog 1 ^'^ 
|L tion in the form of immediate perception 
g of six different kinds. Thus (according^ 



■*■;»'-<* 




"5>"» 



r 

PRAMASACANDRIKA 45 : 

this scbool) it is either conjunction, or inner* 
ence in the conjoined, or inherence in that 
which is inherent in the conjoined, or inher- 
ence, or inherence in the inherent, or the 
relation of qualifying and qualified. Of these, 
conjunction is the contact or relation that 
is effected between the eye and substances like 
jars, etc. (i.e., the relation which brings on the 
perception of substances like jars, etc.). The 
relation of inherence in the conjoined similarly 
exists in the case of colour (which is a quality), 
actions and generic characters. (These inhere in 
substances like jars, dishes, etc., and these latter 
are in conjunction with the eye. Therefore the 
visual perception of colour, action and generic 
character takes place through the relation of *i**'\ 
herence in that which is in conjunction with the 
eye.) In the same way in tactual perception, the 
relation which brings on perception by the tactual <U 
sense is actual conjunction with the tactual sense 
in the case of perception of substances such- W 
as jars, etc., and the relation of inherence in that 
which is in conjunction in the case of the quality 
of touch, the actions and generic characters oT- f;A 
these substances. So also in the case of the 
internal perception of the self' by the mind, the 
relation is conjunction of mind and the &&?%. 
substance in the case of the perception of the latter 
while it is inherence in that which is in conjun|K 
tion in the case of the perception of the pleasure 




46 MADHVA LOGIC 

and pain that exist in the self. So also in the 
case of perception of smell and taste by the 
olfactory and gustatory senses, respectively, the 
relation is inherence in that which is in conjunc- 
tion, the smell and the taste being inherent in| 
substances which are in conjunction respectively 
with the olfactory and gustatory senses. Similar- • 
ly, in the perception of the generic characters of- 
qualities and actions, the relation which mediates^ 
is inherence in that which is inherent in sub- 
stances in conjunction (the generic characters; 
being inherent in the qualities and actions which^ 
are themselves inherent in the substances of wbic$? 
they are qualities and actions). In the perception^ 
of sound By the auditory sense, however, the] 
relation is simple inherence, for the auditory 
sense is nothing but ether or AkaSa as limited^ 
by the tympanum of the ear (sound being a quality 
of Akaia and so inherent in Akaia). (Th^ 
auditory sense being Kka§a itself as limited bjr 
the tympanum and sound being inherent in 
Akaia the relation which holds between sound 
and the auditory sense in the case of perception < 
sound is a relation of pure inherence.) But 
perception of the generic characters, etc., of the 
sound (inherent in particular sounds) is medial 
by the relation of inherence in the inhen 
(sounds being inherent in Akaia and tberefoi 
in the limited AkUa which is the auditory sense, 
and the generic characters, etc., of sounds bein, 



A" 






prama^acandrika 47 

inherent in sounds) . The perception of the absence 
of the jar by the eye takes place through the relation 
of qualification and qualified. In the case of the 
perception in the form i In this place here, there 
is no jar,' the absence of the jar is the qualified 
and the qualification which specifies the absence 
is the particular place or locality with reference 
to which the absence is perceived. (The localisation 
thus acts as the specifying attribute of the absence 
in question.) In the case again of the perception 
of the absence being in the form "This place 
is characterised by the absence of the jar/ 9 the 
place itself acts as the qualified substrate and 
the absence of the jar is regarded as its qualifica- 
tion. Similarly in the perception of Inherence 
itself the mediating relation is that of qualified 
and qualification (Inherence does not inhere. Nor 
is it in conjunction with the objects between which 
it holds. Hence the relation of inherence to the 
objects between which it holds is said to be a 
unique relation which is that of qualification** 
and qualified. The inherence is a qualific3*£ces 
of the objects between which the inherence haesent 
Thus in the case of the inherence of the yhjoga) 
cloth in its parts, viz., the threads, the inhevmen- 
is related to the cloth and the threads by the jition) 
tion of qualification to qualified (and not iom a 
second relation of inherence nor by conjuncti^ Non- 
All this however is fallacious and unteicausal 
Qualities, actions* etc., being nothing apart 



48 MADHVA LOGIC 



■KK 




(i.e., being non-different from) the things qualifi 
or the things acting, etc., a relation of inheren 
between qualities, etc., and their substrates J 
impossible (for inherence presupposes a different 
between the inherent and that in which t" 
inherent inheres). Besides, there is no valifg 
ground for the acceptance of inherence as reafcjj: 
Though the relation of conjunction between /ftp 
self and the mind is required in the case of t" " 
perception of other objects, it is not so requi 
in the perception of the self itself or its propert 
and states, for the self and its properties beii 
the objects presented to the witnessing Intellige 
are not objects of perception by the mind. Ag 
alphabetical sounds being themselves substan 
are, not qualities at all. It cannot be said t 
they cannot be substances as besides ha 
generic characters they are perceptible to 
one of our external senses. For this rule 
according to our view, in the case of dar 
~~>, (Darkness has generic character, is revealed 
„ >>pne of our external senses, and yet is a subs 
^ , not a quality.) And it fails also m 
t of the light of the lamp according to 

j ; of those who hold it to be substantive. <$ 
sound ' t . *., -r^gS 

h th i of the lamp has generic character, 

/ j 3nted to one external sense and yet ugp 
{sounds . - r">^ 

: *ii„ i,ie Naiyayika to consist of nothing but 

in tne i\ f J _ . _ ■<&-■■ ;*^ 

A a 3 which are substances.) Further tbo 

and tne m , _ ._•-' -y -■■m$ 

Iphabetical sounds are qualities of 



T" 



PRAMA^ACANDRIKi 4:9 

r 

Ikafa, yet since as qualities they axe non- 
different from their substrate of AMia, a 
relation of inherence between non-alphabetical 
sounds and Ahtea is impossible. As regards 
the relation of qualification and qualified, it 
being only another name for the relation that 
consists in nothing but the essence of a rela- 
tion itself (svarupasambandha), no separate 
relation of qualification and qualified really 
exists. (Svarupsambandha is the name of 
the relation that consists in the essence or 
svarupa of a relation. Thus inherence is related 
by svarupasambandha to the objects between 
which it holds. This means that the relation 
which relates inherence to its relata is no separate 
relation but the svarupa or essence of the in- 
herence itself.) ■ f ' ' ' 

• But some however say that memory is the 
consciousness that is caused only by traces of past 
experience. The adverb 'only' precludes recogni- 
tion (which arises not simply from traces but also 
require other factors) . Kecognition is the cogni- 
tion that arises from the joint operation of traces 
of past experience and sense-contact with present 
objects. The word coincidence (samprayoga) 
means contact (of sense aod object) . Non-men- 
tion of traces (as a causal condition of recognition) 
will make recognition indistinguishable from a 
simple cognition like 'Here is a jar.' Non- 
mention of coincidence or contact (as a caasal 

7 



50 MADHVA LOGIC [thU^k 

condition) will again make recognition indis* 
tinguishable from memory. . \> 

; The above view is not tenable. For all 
valid knowledge is due to a valid ground or 
source of knowledge and therefore since memory 
is one kind of valid knowledge, the cause of 
memory, viz. z the traces of past experience, will 
have to be admitted as an independent pramana 
or ground of true knowledge. But in this case 
the number of pramanas or valid sources of 

i 

knowledge will be four and this is unestablished 
(as we have seen that the number is three and 
neither more nor less). It cannot be said that 
the objection applies also to our view (of recollec- 
tion or memory). We hold memory to be due 
to internal perception by the mind with con 
tration of attention (bhavana) as an auxiliary 
condition. (Hence in our view memory is M 
form of perception, a kind of intellectual intuition 
where the trace of the past experiences serves 
function of contact of the present mind with t 
past experience. Thus according to our view* 
though memory is admitted to be a form of 
knowledge, it is regarded only as a variety 
perception, and so the cause of memory is not 
separate source of knowledge, though no doubt | 
is a ground of true knowledge.) „ ..; 

There are four kinds of perception (as a 
of valid knowledge), viz., the Lord's percepti© 
the Consort's perception, the perception ,th«» ;^ 

. ■- 



. •?* 



v *.jk 



3 



~B 




PRAMA^ACANDRIKA 5l 

belongs to the Yogin or Seer, and the perception 
that belongs to an ordinary mortal (ayogin). 
The objects of these different kinds of perception 
are the same as the objects of the corresponding 
cognitions or experiences which each kind induces 
in its respective perceiver. For fuller details the 
reader is referred to Jayatirtha's Pramana- 
paddhati (which we think unnecessary to go into 
over again here). Thus everything (relating to 
perception) has been set forth and therefore we 
close our chapter on perception as expounded in 
this Pramanaeandrika on the lines chalked out 
by the revered Jayatirtha. We bend our heads 
in respect to the sage Vyasadeva. ^ 

Let us now proceed to the next Pramaija, ©&.>> 
Inference. Inference is flawless reasoning, flawless 
establishment or proof of a conclusion (by means 
of a reason or ground). The synonyms of proof 
are reasoning, arguing from a mark to the thing 
marked, concluding on the basis of something 
which is pervaded by an invariable relation to 

something else. 

Inference cannot be defined simply as reason- 
ing or arguing from a mark, for the definition 
would then apply to fallacious reasonings such as 
those where the subject of the inference is 
fictitious or unreal and where the mark is known 
by a valid source of knowledge to exdwlr 
'(instead of being invariably related to) the thing 
marked. In these cases the reasonings are 



52 MADHVA LOGIC 

< 

grounded on an invariable correlation and yet the 
reasonings are fallacious. (In the former, though 
the invariable relation holds, the subject of the 
inference is non-existent and thus the locus in 
which the relation is to prove the existence of the 
probandum does not exist. In the latter, the 
invariable relation is asserted in the reasoning 
but in actual fact no such relation holds, and 
thus the conclusion lacks material truth.) Hence 
inference is defined not as reasoning merely, but 
as flawless reasoning. Nor again can inference be. 
defined simply as that which is flawless for in, 
this case the definition will apply equally to' 
Perception as a source of knowledge. Hence it is , 
defined as reasoning (which is flawless). 

The instrumental cause of inference is the 
sign or mark (by means of which we infer the 
'•■;- probandum). The operation or process (of the 
instrumental cause) which leads to or establishes 
th$ collusion is reasoning or argumentation (i.e.,; 
reasoning by means of the sign through which the ■■ 
"subject of the inference is brought in relation to* j 
the probandum). The inferred conclusion is the J 
result which emerges out of the process. Keason4 : : l 
ing (Paramaria) consists in the cognition of the 
mark in the form of its invariable relation to ther;? 
probandum as a property of the subject of thet^ 
inference. For example in the inference of. fire 
in yonder mountain from the perception of smoke : 



therein, the reasoning consists in cognition ot 



-.-■:■ 

-'■■■■■ 






& -; 



PRAMAljrACANDRIKA 



53 



the smoke as an invariable concomitant of fire and 
as being, as so invariably related, a property of the 
mountain yonder. The cognition which results 
from the process, viz. f yonder mountain is on fire, 
is the resulting inference. Invariable relation 
means invariable concomitance (or sequence) as in 
the case * wherever there is smoke, there is fire/ 
By concomitance or co-existence is here meant a 
relation merely between the ground of the infer- 
ence and its probandunu By the invariableness 
of the concomitance is not meant then co-inher- 
ence in the same substrate. The invariableness 
of the concomitance means simply that the con- 
comitance is fixed and unfailing. The purport of 
the whole is that vyapti or invariable 
comitance consists in an unfailing 
between the ground of the inference 
probandum. It follows therefore t 
essential character (the defining mark) 
consists in the unfailing regularity of 
tance (between two or more phenomena), 
when we observe that wherever smoke is per- 
ceived, there fire also is perceived, we are said to 
cognise the relation of vyapti or invariable con- 
comitance between 'smoke' and 'fire.' Here 
* smoke f is the pervaded and fire the pervading 
property. The locus or abode of the invariable 
relation is called the pervaded wlnle that which 
defines or marks off the relation is called the 
pervading. [Thus if A is invariably related 




V: 



54 MADHVA LOGIC 

to B, A as the locus of the invariable relation 
is the pervaded, while B as defining or mark- 
ing off this (particular) invariable relation 
from other invariable relations is the pervading' 
or pervader.] By the pervaded being a property i| 
of the subject of the inference is meant its; 
existence in a suitable place (so as to make 
its invariable relation with the pervader pos-- A 
sible. It does not mean that the pervaded | 
property should be spatially or temporally includ- 
ed within the pervader). And thus our theory i 
is free from flaws even of a trivial character. ' 

Some however give the following account olM 
invariable concomitance. Invariable concomi^j|| 
tance (as an element or factor of inference) means; || 
the coinherence of the ground and the probandum 
in one and the same locus so that the probandumM 
can never be that which is negated by theg| 
absolute negation that coinheres in the locus of thep 
ground of the inference and also does not coinhenfe 
in the locus of that which it negates. (In othe^ 
words, if the probandum is not that which; *8| 
negated by the absolute negation that occupies thfl| 
place where the ground exists and also does not 
occupy the place where the object negated by th^ 
said absolute negation exists, then the relation 
coexistence in the same locus between the grot; 
and the probandum is an invariable relation.) 

Mere coexistence with the probandum inl- 
and the same locus does not fully bring out t 



PRAMAtfACANDRIKA 55. 

nature of vyapti or invariable relation. Take the 
inference, f. i., "Yonder mountain is on fire, 
because it has the character of knowableness." 
Here coexistence in the same locus holds 
(between the ground, * knowableness/ and the 
probandum, 'fire,', i.e., the locus of ** fire/ 
e.g., the 'oven/ is also the locus of knowable 
ness, i.e., the oven is a knowable object) . And 
yet the inference is evidently fallacious. To 
exclude such cases, the probandum (coexistence 
wherewith will constitute vyapti) is qualified 
as being one which is not that which is 

; negated by the absolute negation which occupies 
the place where the ground or H etu exists. 
(This qualification of the probandum excludes the 
case of the above fallacious inference and other 
like cases- For -fire/ the probandum of the 

; above inference, is that which is negated by the 
absolute negation occupying the place where the 
ground, viz., ' knowableness,' exists; e.g., fire: 
never exists in the great lake and yet ' knowable- 
ness * exists in> the great lake in so far as the lake 
is a knowable object. Therefore the probandum* 
'fire/ is not that which is absolutely non-existing 

I . where the ground, ' knowableness/ exists.) Even 
this qualification of the probandum, however, fails. 

-to exclude the case of (the evidently fallacious), 
inference, "The tree is in contact (with the; 
monkey) because it has the generic character ol£ ; 
substances." (Here 'contact ' is the probmdfym^; 



v 



': 



56 MADHVA LOGIC 

and it is not that which is absolutely non-existent 
where the hetu, or ground, viz., 'the generic | 
character of substances,' exists. 'The generic 
character of substances * exists in substances. 
* Contact * as a quality also exists in substances. 
Hence ' contact ' is not that which is absolutely 
non-existent in substances. And yet the inference 
is fallacious.) To exclude such cases the proban- 
dum is further qualified as being one which also 
does not coexist in the same substrate with that 
which is absolutely non-existent where the ground 
or hetu exists. This excludes the case of c contact l 
and the like. ['Contact' abides in substances. 
It is thus not that which is absolutely non- 
existent in substances. But despite this, contact 
is also not that which does not coexist with that 
which is absolutely non-existent in substances. || 
For 'contact* coexists with the absence of con* 
tact in the same substance. 'Contact' of thft 
tree and monkey coexists in the tree with th% ^ 
negation or absence of such contact in another 
part of the tree. 'Contact' thus coexists with ; .gs 
non-contact (with the absolute negation of 
contact) in one and the same substrate.] Iff im 
other words, non-contact or negation of cotti-^ 
tact being coexistent in the same substratft|| 
or substance with contact which is the object 
of the negation, the rule, that the probandum 
should not exist in the same substrate with 
that which . is absolutely non-existent when* 



■ -;■; 



% 



■■-3"* 



*& 



t- i 



■fe 



'*>*"&§& 



PRAMAtfACANDBlKl IJ 

the ground exists, fails, and the case cannot 
be regarded as one of invariable relation or 

vyapti. ■'■''■ 

But all this, we hold, is fallacious and un- 
sound. Take the case of the inference ' There is 
rain on the hills higher up because the rivers 
below are full.' Here from the fullness of the 
rivers at the base we infer the occurrence of rain 
at the top. In such inferences, where the 
probandum occupies a different place from that 
occupied by the prolans or ground, the above 
definition of invariable concomitance as co- 
existence, in the same substrate, of the ground 
and the probandum altogether fails. It cannot be 
said that our view is open to the self-same objec- 
tion as the above view, for unfailing relation of 
effect and cause holds equally, in our view, in the 
ease of inferences where the prolans and the 

probandum occupy different places. ^ .... , 

.. (We have so far discussed the meaning of 
invariable relation. We now proceed to explairi 
the different forms of invariable relation that 
constitute the grounds of inference.) Dharmas 
or properties of things may be related in four 
different ways. Thus two Dharmas or properties 
may be related by a positive symmetrical invariable 
relation so that each is invariably concomitant 
with the other. Two properties again may 
be so related that one of them is an invariable 
concomitant of the other, but not vice versa. 

:.:-./.,■ 8; •.."'■'• ■■:..• . • .'. ,' m- 



-„*i 






58 MADHVA LOGIC 

Two properties again may be invariably related 
by the relation of mutual negation and exclu- 
sion. Lastly, two properties may be so^jj 
related that at least in one case where one is, the 
other is, as also at least in one case where either ^ 
one is, the other is not. (This last relation is i 
equal to the following three propositions taken 
together where A and B express the two properties, 
viz., ' At least in one case where A is, B is ' ' At 
least in one case where A is, B is not/ ' At least ■* 
in one case where B is, A is not.' The first 
form of concomitance is similarly equal to the;| 
two propositions — 'Wherever A is, Bis,' and 
Wherever B is, A is/— taken together. The second 
and the third will correspond respectively to the 
propositions € In all cases where A is, B is ' and 
'In no case where A is, B is.') We have av| 
concrete illustration of the first form of invariable 
concomitance in the unfailing relation that holds 
between scriptural (Vedic) prohibition and con- f\ 
duciveness to demerit and sin and between scrip- J 
tural injunction and conduciveness to merit and 
righteousness . Thus whatever is scripturally 
prohibited is productive of sin and demerit and 
whatever tends to demerit and sin is scripturafly:.;! 
prohibited. Here each of the two (related 
properties)' is at once pervaded by, and pervader | 
of, the other. Similarly it is] also observed thsk| 
whatever is scripturally enjoined is also conducive 
to merit and righteousness and whatever is 



:-:m 



PRAMAtfACANDRIKi 59 

conducive to merit and righteousness is also laid 
down by scripture. The second form of invari- 
able concomitance is again illustrated in the case 
of the relation between smoke and fire, as also 
between the product of will and non-eternity. 
Thus ( wherever there is smoke, there is fire * but 
no invariable relation holds in the form ' Where- 
ever there is fire, there is smoke,' for in the case 
of the heated iron-ball (where fire is, but smoke 
is not) the invariability fails. Here ' smokiness p 
is- the pervaded and occupies a smaller area while 
' fireness * is the pervader and occupies a wider 
area. Similarly, 'whatever is a product of 
will-causality is also non-eternal,' but no in- 
variable relation holds in the form of the converse 
of this, viz., 'whatever is non-eternial, is also a 
product of will-causality,' for it is seen to fail in 
the case of antecedent non-existence (which is 
non-eternal and yet is no product of will- 
causality). The third form of invariable con- 
comitance is illustrated in the relation which 
holds between the generic character of the cow and 
the generic character of the horse as also between 
that of the elephant and that of the lion. Thus 
wherever there is the generic character of the cow, 
there is nowise the generic character of the horse 
and wherever there is the generic character of the 
horse there is nowise the generic character of the 
cow. No relation of pervader and pervaded holds 
betwAPn *\thaT mio and thfl other, all relation 



*• 



so 



MADHVA LOGIC 



: being non-existent between the two. Simila; 
~ T whatever is an elephant, is nowise a lion' ar 
' whatever is a lion, is nowise an elephant' 
well-known mutually exclusive relations to 
noted in this connection. The fourth kind 
invariable concomitance is illustrated in the 
case of the relation which exists between tbe 
the property of being a cook and the property of; 
a man as also between the property of being 
one of the five elements and the property 
moving. Thus though in one particular ins 
the property of being a cook and the prop 
.of being a man may co-exist, yet in another 
the property of being a cook may co-exist 
that of being a woman to the exclusion of 
of being a man as also in a third instance 
property of being a man may co-exist with t 
property of being a non-cook to the exclusion 
the property of being a cook. In this case 
-no relation of pervader and pervaded 
between either one and the other, for inspite 
a relation existing between the two, there 
instances in which the relation fails. In the 
way, though the property of being an ele 
is co-existent in some instances with the pro 
of moving {viz., in earth, water, air and 
yet in the case of Skaia or ether (which is 
element but does not move) the property of being; 
an element exists to the exclusion of the pro 
of movingi and in the case of the mind 



■::"":-H9 



v^ 





property of moving exists to the 

of the property of being an element. 

is not an element and yet it moves.) , . ■ . ■ > 

In all these when the property which is per- 
vaded produces the cognition of the property that 
is the pervader, we have what is called an in- 
ference or anumana* The pervading property (of 
which the inference produces the knowledge) is 
called the inferred character, anumeya, or object 

of inference. 

The following objection may however be 
raised to the view of inference expounded above, 
viz., that it is not possible for the smoke that 
exists in the mountain far away to produce a 
valid cognition of fire in the man who exists 
here in his house. The reply to this objection is 
as follows. In the case of inference the instru- || 
mental cause is a known agency and not an im- ■•* ' 
known condition as in the case of perceptioa^ 
(The relation of smoke to fire is known to the man|^^ 
who makes the inference, but in perception the 
action of the sensibilities with reference to the 









*W* 



*8 






object perceived is not known before the P«^|M 
ception.) - ■ ■ "'~;*&ea#' 

The reply however does not seem to be coff- - 
vincing, for there are people (e.g., the savage**!^ 
the Cocoanut Island) in whom the perception-of 
smoke at a distance does not call forth the 
cognition of fire. The answer is that m $Hs 
case though they have a cognition of the form of 



■ -,vl 

*i 

■V ■ 

■ *i 
' " 



62 mIdHVA LOGIC 

the smoke, yet they have no knowledge of it as an 
invariable concomitant of fire. For even when 
an object like smoke might previously be cognised 
as an invariable concomitant of something else 
such as fire, it may fail to be cognised on account 
of failure of memory as an invariable concomitant 
of the latter in a fresh instance and thus fail to 
produce the cogniton of fire. (Therefore in the 
case of savages where the smoke was never cog- 
nised as invariably related to fire, a cognition of 
smoke in the first instance cannot possibly 
produce the knowledge of fire.) 

Therefore we conclude : when an accurately 
and correctly cognised mark or sign is accom- 
panied by a recollection of its invariable con- ;| 
comitance with the thing marked or signified M 
and is thereby able to produce the cognition of 
the thing marked or signified in a fit place or 
locality, we have what is called an inference or ,| 
*anumana. Hence even though the form of the^jj 
marked or signified thing may be already known : | 
yet since the inference makes it known further in 
relation to a particular place or locality, the|| 
inferential process is not useless or superfluous. 
(The inference, in other words, entails a real 
march of thought conducing as it does to a:| 
new synthesis of the already known thing with a :| 
place or situation to which it was not previously 
known to be related.) Hence inference consists 
of two factors: (1) invariable concomitance .(of 



1 



£Z 



t 



% 



3ft 



srsE 






PRAMAtfACANDRIKA 63 

■ 

the mark with the thing marked) ; (2) the 
presence of the mark in a suitable place such 
as will make possible the inference of the 
thing marked either in the same place or some 
other (causally or otherwise connected) place. 
There is no rule that the mark should also 
be cognised as a property existing in the subject 
of the inference (for the mark may exist in 
one place, e.g., the fullness of the rivers at 
the base, and the thing marked, viz., rain, may 
be proved to exist in some other place, e.g., at the 
top of the hill). 

A question here arises : how does the cognition 
of the invariable concomitance arise? How in 
other words, do we arrive at the knowledge of an 
invariable concomitance between different objects 
or events ? The answer is, by means of the 
corresponding perceptions, inferences and testi- 
mony. Thus in the case of the invariable con- 
comitance of smoke and fire, we arrive at the 
knowledge of the concomitance of smoke with fire 
by the perception of the one together with the 
other in the domestic oven and other places. 
Here repeated observation and non -observation of 
the contrary are the auxiliary conditions. But 
how can perception which apprehends only that 
which is present and is in contact with the 
sensibilities, apprehend an invariable concomitance 
that extends not merely to all cases (actual 
and possible) but also to the past (and the 



64 



MADHVA LOGIC 



: T"' ■ 



future and the remote) ? It would be possib 
if you admitted a transcendental cont 
(pratyasatti) of past and present and of h 
and far (as Naiyayikas do), but according 
to you, no such transcendental contact exists 
(between the present sense organ and the past 
and distant objects). The answer to this is:. 
though there is no transcendental contact between J 
a particular instance and its samanya or classg 
yet since the past and the distant are capable 
being drawn into relation to the present instan ? 
by means of similarity or resemblance, the cognj| 
tion of an invariable concomitance as extendi ' 
to all instances (actual and possible) is ful|| 
established. Invariable concomitance as m 
known mediately by means of inference will 
illustrated later on. The following are inst 
of invariable concomitance known from authj»« 
tative testimony. 'Whoever is a Brahmin, 
person who must not be put to death,' ' 
animal that is a cow is one that must not 1 
touched with the feet,' ' Whatever is enjoined j 

. the Vedas, ought to be accomplished as a duty/ | 
Inference is of three kinds: inference *^ 
effects, inference from causes, and inferenceJroi|J 
phenomena that are neither causes 
When an effect is the ground of our inference 
the cause, we have an inference from an effi 
e.g., when from the presence of smoke we J| 

p the existence of fire. When the cause 



'-** »\ -' 









PRAMAtfACANDWKl 65 

the ground of an inference of the effeet, we have 
an inference from a cause, e.g., when we say, 
'yonder mass of clouds which owes its special 
character to its own cause proves an impending 
rain-fall.' When a particular mark proves the 
existence of a probandum without being either 
the cause or the effect of it, we have an inference 
from something which is neither a cause nor an 
effect, e.g., when the presence of taste proves the,, 
existence of colour. 

Inference may be divided again into two 
classes from another standpoint, viz., into infer- 
ence of what is specifically observed and inference 
of what is generically observed. Thus whei*|*he 
object inferred is perceptible we have an inference 
of the specifically observed, e.g., when &»» 
inferred from smoke. Where the object inferred 
is not perceptible, we have an inference of the, 
generically observed, e.g., when the visual, 

; sensibility is inferred from the cognition of colour. 

Some (the Naiyayikas) hold that inference is 

of three kinds, viz., Kevalanvayl inference, 

i Kevalavyatireki inference and AnvayavyatireMM 

r m 

inference. ;,: 

(According to the Naiyayikas) the pakja or the 
;*; subject of an inference is that substrate which is 

to be proved to own the, probandum as its property. 

To exclude the sapaksa or the co-ordinate o*H^ 
Isttbject and other like substrates, the subject is 

defined as that which is to own the proband*** as a 

tfer,- 9 - ., • •■ .■■■■'■ 



:■?-- t 



'C- 



% 






"z 



*■* 



m 



66 = 'MADHVX LOGIC 

property. Since the property here means that the $| 
cognition whereof is to be produced by the sign 
or mark (in the inference), the definition is not too 
wide. (The sapaksa is also a substrate of a pro- 
perty, but it is not the substrate of the property 
the cognition whereof is to be produced by the mark 
or sign. It is the substrate of a property which 
is homogeneous with the property that constitutes 
the probandum, but it is not the substrate of the 
property which is the probandum itself.). But it 
may be said that the hetu or ground has also this 
character of being characterised by the probwndum^^ 
as being related to it by conjunction (and thus the | 
definition is too wide as applying to the hetu or ^ 
ground as well). To meet this objection the J 
paksa has been defined as a substrate. (The hetu : r$ 
is not the substrate of the property that constitutes J| 
the probandum, but is related to it only by J .^| 
concomitance or conjunction, but the paksa 
is the substrate in which the probandum is to 
be proved to abide as a property.) The 
sapaksa or co-ordinate of the inferential subject is 
that substrate which owns a property which is 
homogeneous with that which constitutes the 
probandum. To preclude a too wide application^ 1 
to the case of the smoke in the oven, the definition 
includes the word 'substrate.' [The smoke in the 
oven is the familiar instance or drstanta and n 

• * # 

the sapaksa. It is distinguished from the la 
by the fact that it is not the substrate, while 



m 







PRAMAtfACANDBIKA 67 

sapaksa is the substrate of a property (in this 
case the kitchen fire) homogeneous with the 
property constituting the probandum (i.e., the fire 
in the mountain)]. To have defined the sapaksa 
simply as the substrate of the probandum (and not 
of a property homogeneous with the probandum) 
would have been absurd. (For the sapaksa and 
the paksa would in that case have been identical, 
and a sapaksa other than the pak§a would have 
been an impossibility.) Therefore in the defini- 
tion the word ' homogeneous ' has been included. 
The meaning is that the sapaksa is the substrate 
of a property homogeneous with the probandum 
and as such is devoid of the character of 
uncertainty (i.e., the uncertainty that characterizes 
the paksa as the substrate of the probandum). V 
The vipaksa or contra-ordinate of the inferential '^ 
subject is a substrate devoid alike of the pro- 
bandum and every property homogeneous with 
the probandum. The words ' devoid of the pro* 
bandum' distinguishes the vipaksa from the 
paksa while the words ' devoid of every property, 
homogeneous with the probandum' distinguishes 
it from the sapaksa. (The sapaksa is a similar 
instance in which the existence of a pror^iy like 
the probandum is known for certain, and the 
vipaksa is a dissimilar instance in which the 
non-existence of the probandum and of all 
properties similar to the probandum is known 
for certain.) ;■-," ;.'*-.■:>;'■ ; ' '-'■ '- - 



68 MADHVA LOGIC 

[These definitions of the inferential subject, 
the co-ordinate of the inferential subject and the 
contra-ordinate to the inferential subject, prepare 
the way for the definitions of Kevalanvayi and 
other forms of inference.] 

Thus the Kevalanvayi inference is one which 
is based on a ground that pervades the subject 
and also exists in its co-ordinates but which has J 
no contra-ordinate to its subject actually existing. 
[In other words, a Kevalanvayi inference is one | 
that is based on numerous instances of agreement- 
in presence but is without any instance of agree- 
ment in absence.] - ^ 

Kevalanvayi inference cannot be defined 

simply as an inference in which there existed 
no co-ordinate to the subject, for in this case if ;; 
will be indistinguishable from the inconclusive 
reasoning 'All things are nameable, because theyg 
are knowable.' (Here the subject of the inference 
being 'all things' or 'everything/ no eontraN^ 
ordinate to the subject exists, but since there is 
here also no co-ordinate to it, the ground of the 
inference, viz., the invariable relation between 
* knowableness ' and ' nameableness/ is without a 
corroborative familiar instance and thus lacks 
material certitude.) Hence the words *in whi 

the ground is existent in the co-ordinate.* 
even thus the definition remains imperfect for 
inference which has no <x>ntra-ordinate to its 
ject and in which the ground is existent a3m 



Y«jp : iki 



H' 



Swh 







Prama^acandbikI 6$ 

f*w- ■ 

Ithe co-ordinate, is not distinguishable from the 

I fallacious reasoning in which the ground does not 

Sexist in the subject of the inference, e.g., the 
inference 'sound is nameable because it is visible.' 
To exclude such fallacious reasonings Kevalanvayi 
inference is further specified by the qualification 
that it is an inference in which the ground must 
exist in the subject. Even this, however, 
is not sufficient, for this by itself does not 
distinguish it from such fallacious reasonings 
as ' The jar and sound are nameable, for they 
are characterised by shape' where the ground, 

''?■ viz., 'shape,' exists only in one part of the subject, 
viz., the 'jar,' and not in the other part, viz.? 

ft 'sound.' To exclude such fallacious reasonings 

land prevent these being confounded with 
Kevalanvayi inference, the ground is stated as 

{ being not merely existent in the subject but also 
as pervading it. The pervasion of the subject 

£ may again be of two forms, viz., (1) Where the 
ground pervades both the subject and its eo-' 

* . ordinates, and (2) where the ground pervades the 
subject but exists only in a portion (i.e., in some) 

i-0f the co-ordinates. > Sound is namable, because* 
is knowable, just as is the jar' illustrates the case 
where the ground pervades not merely the subject 
but also its co-ordinates. In the same reasoning 
the words 'because it is a quality just as is colour 
On place of the words 'because it is knowaWe 

IP* as is the jar ') illustrates the case where the 



m. 






70 



MADHVA LOGIC 




ground exists only hrsome (i.e. a portion of 1 
entire extent) of the co-ordinates. (The gro\& 
viz., 'quality' is predicable of some nameabl 
things, but not of all narneable things.) 

The invariable concomitance which constitu 
the ground of inference is of two kinds, viz., in- 
variable concomitance as agreement in presence 
and invariable concomitance as agreement fe 
absence. Invariable concomitance as agreement 
in presence consists in the invariable confj 
comitance of the ground of the inference with 
the probandum. Invariable concomitance 
agreement in absence consists in the invariabli 
concomitance of the absence of the probandm 
with the absence of the ground. In the case 
agreement in presence, the ground is the pervad 
and fhe probandum is the pervader. In the 
of agreement in absence, the absence of the pro-- 
bandum is the pervaded and the absence of t 
ground the pervader. In every case an invariable 
concomitance is understood as following in t 
wake of the pervaded. In the case of the abov^ 
inference ' sound is narneable, because it is know- 
able, just as is the jar,' the invariable 

' knowable ' with ' narneable * 
agreement in presence only. T] 
presence here is ' whatever 
narneable, just as is the jai 
no agreement in absence 
1 what is not narneable is 



cam 



comitance of 
based on an 
agreement in 
knowable, is 
But we have 
the form 



.. M + +; 



in 







PBAMi^TACANDRIKA. 71 

knowable,' it being impossible to get any 
case of an object which is not nameable as 
illustrative of such absence, since all things are 
nameable and there is nothing that is not name- 
able. This is why inference based on such con- 
comitance consisting of agreement in presence 
only is called inference of the Kevalanvayi type. 
Where the ground pervades the subject, where no 
co-ordinate of the subject exists and where further 
the ground is excluded from every instance of a 
contra-ordinate to the subject, we have an inference 
of the Kevalamjatirekl type (according to Nyaya). 
If Kevalavyatirekl inference had been defined as 
one in which the ground is excluded from (some 
instances of) the contra-ordinate to the subject, 
the definition would have been too wide and 
would have applied to the fallacious reasoning 
based on a non-invariable ground, 'yonder moun- 
tain is on fire, because it is a mountain.' To ex- 
clude such reasonings the definition lays down that 
the ground must be excluded from every instance 
of a contra-ordinate to the subject. In the present 
case, the ground, viz., 'being a mountain,' though 
excluded from such contra-ordinates as 'the great 
lake,' 'the sheet of water,' etc., is yet not excluded 
from such other contra-ordinates as 'a fireless 
mountain/ 'a hill without fire.' Hence the ground 
is not excluded 'from every case of a contra-ordinate 
to the subject' and thus does not come up to - the 
requirements of the definition (of a Kevalavyatireki 



:V« 



72 



MADHVA LOGIC 






inference as set forth above). Thus the defi 
does not apply to such cases and is not too wi 
(as applying to such fallacious reasonings as wel 
It must be noted however that the mere fact of 
ground being excluded from every instance of 
contra-ordinate or dissimilar instance does no 
suffice as a complete definition of the Kevatid. 
vyatirekl inference, for as such it remains 
distinguished from Anvayavyatirekl inferen 
based both on agreement in presence and agre 
ment in absence. To exclude such inferen 
the definition stresses the fact that ' no 
ordinate of the subject should exist,' i.e., 
similar instance where the existence of the pro 
bandum should be known for certain should e 
(In Anvayavyatireki inference, the existence of t| 
co-ordinate or similar instance is a sine qu& n 
while , in Kevalavyatireki the non-existence 

. $hs> co-ordinate is a sine qud non.) Bute 
this added qualification does not suffice aig 
definition of the Kevalavyatireki inference, 
as such it has a too wide application to 
fallacious inference based on a Svarupasi 
ground (i.e., on a ground that does not exu 

*in the inferential subject), viz., 'The 
of the finite individual has a soul aceo$ 
panyingit, since this body is conscious. '.... 
the ground, viz., 'consciousness' is non-existent 
the ' body ' which is the inferential subject, 
dead body, e.g., is devoid of consciousness. 



1 













S.1' • 



PRA&f AtfACANDBIKl 73' 

exclude such cases, the definition insists on the 
existence of the ground in the subject. Even 
this, however, does not suffice, for as so qualified 
the definition applies to the fallacious inference 
based on a ground that exists in one part of the 
subject (and not in the whole of it), viz., "The 
finite individual and the Lord are omniscient, 
because they are all-creating." (Here the ground 
'all-creating' is true only of the Lord and not of 
the finite individual, i.e., it holds good of one part 
of the subject and not of the whole of it,) To 
exclude such cases the definition says, 'The 
ground must pervade the subject.' The following 
is an instance of a Kevalavyatireki in£ 
answering to all the above requirement 
Lord is all-knowing, because He is alft^^ting/ „v^Jr 
It is based on the invariable agreement/if £bsen<^ j> 
viz., 'Whatever is not all-knowing, is ^n^ 1 ^ J£ 
creating, just as is Devadatta.' 
innumerable instances illustrating this a 
in absence but none illustrating the positive 
ment in presence between ' what is all-creating ' and 
'what is all-knowing,' for Kamkr§na and other 
Incarnations of the Lord are comprised in the 
subject of the inference (and therefore cannot serve 
as corroborative illustrations) while other finite 
individuals are non-omniscient (and therefore 
cannot be cited as illustrations of the agreement 
in presence). For these reasons (©«., that it is 
based on an invariable relation which can be 

10 




74 



MADHVA LOGIC 



:&S : 



actually observed only as agreement in absence! 
and not as agreement in presence) such inference | 
is called kevalavyatireki inference. 

An inference in which the ground pervades the 
subject, exists in the co-ordinates or known similar 
instances wherein the probandum exists, and is ex- .| 
eluded from every instance of a contra-ordinate to 
the subject is an anvayavyatireki inference. An.'-$ 
anvayavyatireki inference is not completely defined fl 
as one in which the ground is found to be non- 
existent in the contra-ordinates, for as such the 
definition fails to exclude the fallacious inference 
based on a non-invariable ground, viz., ' The body I 
of the finite individual is non-eternal, because it 
has the character of the element of earth.' In this 
inference the ground, viz., 'character of the 
element of earth,' though non-existent in such|f§ 
eternal entities as the ether, etc., is yet existent ii 
such other eternal entities as the atoms of earth^j 
etc. (Thus though excluded from some objects 
which are not non-eternal, it is yet not excluded 
from some other objects which are also not non-1 
eternal.) To exclude such cases, the definitioi|| 
says, ' the ground must be excluded from ever^ 
instance of a contra-ordinate.' But this also by 
itself does not suffice as a complete definitioi 
for as such it remains indistinguishable from 
kevalavyatireki inference based on agreement I 
in absence only. Hence the definition adds il 
words, ' the ground must exist in the co-ordinates! 



V- 





tRAMAtfACAND&IKA 16 

ffi- (The kevalavyatireki is devoid of co-ordinates.} 

Even with this added qualification, the definition 
if" has a too wide application to the fallacious 
;, : " inference based on a svar&pasiddha ground (i.e., a 
| ground that does not exist in the subject), viz., 
;•• 'Devadatta is all-knowing, because he is all- 
V. creating.' (Here the ground 'all-creating' is 

excluded from all cases of 'not all-knowing' and 
:V also exists in 'what is all-knowing,' viz., the 
J:.-' Lord. But it does not exist in Devadatta, the 
|- subject of the (inference). Hence the defini- 
| tion further adds, 'the ground must exist in ■■ 

the subject.' Even now however the definition ; ; 
\y. applies to the fallacious inference based on y 
&,a bhagasiddha ground (i.e. , a ground that exists; .;;? 

only in one part of the subject and not the whole 
I of it), viz., ' The mountain and the lake are oafW" 
%' fire, because they smoke.' (Here the ground,^ 
J' smoke' exists in one part of the subject, tiz.^y 
J •: 'mountain,' and not in the other part, viz., the £| 

'lake.') To exclude such cases the definition 
jfc* says 'the ground must pervade (i.e., exist in the, 
f§ whole of) the subject.' As 'smokiness' is 

absent in the 'lake' (being true only of the 
h 'mountain ') it lacks the character of pervading 
H the subject (in the above case) . . ''"-^M 

Such anvayavyatireki inference based bo^jg 

on agreement in presence and agreement in 
H absence may again be of two kinds. 33«^ v 
i.«tf .<• « inference with a ground that . 



-*; 



^:- 



l 9m 






u 



MADHVA LOGIC 



# 



■A 



exists in every case of a co-ordinate, or aga 
it may be an inference with a ground t 
exists only in some (not all) instances of 
co-ordinates. For example, the inference, 'The 
finite individual is eternal, because there is no 
cause that can put an end to it' is a case; 
of an anvayavyatireki inference with a ground 
existing in all cases of the co-ordinates. W\ 
respect of all eternal things such as the ether, 
etc., the ground, viz., ' absence of a cause of| 
an end or destruction ' holds good. Again, the 
inference ' The mountain is on fire, because it- 
smokes ' is an instance of an anvayavyatireki 
inference with a ground that exists only in some 
(and not all) its co-ordinates, for in some ' fiery V 
things (e.g., the red-hot iron ball) ' smoke 1 
(which is the ground of the inference) does not 
exist. This latter example is a typical anvaya- 
vyatireki inference and takes its name from the 
following two invariable relations (of presence 
and absence) on which it is based, viz., 'What- 
ever smokes, is on fire, just as is the oven ' anig 
' Whatever is not on fire, does not smoke, just 

as is the great lake.' ' ■ ?|jj 

Inferences based on agreement in presence 
and agreement in absence take their character 
from the corresponding invariable concomi 
Thus we have invariable concomitance based o 
agreement in presence in * Wherever there 
smoke, there is fire.' And we have invari 



fc PBAMA^ACANDBIKA 



77 



concomitance based on agreement in absence in 
'Wherever fire is not, smoke is not.' And 
inferences that resemble these two forms of 
concomitances considered together are called 
Anvayavyatireki Inferences or inferences based on 
agreement in presence and agreement in absence. 

All this however (i.e., this division of inference 
into kevalanvayi, kevalavyatireki and anvaya- 
vyatireki) we (the Madhvas) reject as untenable. 
For we consider an agreement in absence as being 
unsuitable for proving the presence of the sadhya 
or probandum. In proving the presence of a 
positive entity by means of the presence of 
another positive (entity), an invariable relation 
between the absence of one and the absence of 
the other has no logical scope. (An m-' 
variable relation between the negation of one 
thing and the negation of another does not 
justify any positive step from the presence of one 
to the presence of the other.) For in this case 
the positive ground exists in the subject of the 
inference (and thus falls within the domain of 
affirmation) while the invariable relation as an 
agreement in absence (the absence of the proban- 
dum and the absence of the ground) belongs to the 
domain of negation and thus occupies a different 
place. Thus the invariable relation occupies one 
place (the domain of negation) and the ground as a 
property of the subjeot occupies a different place 
(the domain of affirmation). (Hence there 18 no 



78 MADHVA LOGIC 

relation between the two to justify an inferenti 
step.) How then, it may be asked, are kevala4 
vyatireki inferences in vogue? In this way.^ 
Here also the real ground is an invariable relation 
in presence, e.g., the invariable relation between 
'omniscience ' and ' all-creativeness ' in the above 
inference. But it is impossible to cite positive 
similar instances of this agreement in presence in 
response to the demand for an indication of the ■% 
actual places where this invariable relation holds. 
Hence for accomplishing this end by means of 
inference, an invariable relation of absence ac- 
quires relevancy (for our purpose). For example, 
if in the above instance it is asked: — "What 
proof have we of an invariable relation between 
' all-creativeness ' and ' omniscience ? " w6g 
can say at once that 'all-creativeness' must 
be pervaded by 'omniscience,* for it ift|| 
that which is negated by the negation which 
pervades the negation of 'omniscience.' When 
one thing is so related to another thing that the 
negation of the former pervades the negation of 
the latter, the former thing is invariably relatafij 
to the latter. (Thus if A is so related to B that 
the negation of A is pervasive of the negation of 
B, i.e., if 'All not-B is not-A,' then A is invaria 
related to B, i.e., 'All A is B.') This relation is 
admitted, e.g., by the person seeking 'fire,' 
holding between ' smokiness ' and ' fireness^ 
In the case of the so-called dtwayavyatire^^ 




ft*?--' 



PRAMAtf ACANDRIKA 79 

inferences supposed to be based on agreements in 

% presence as well as absence, the agreement in 
absence is in reality purposeless and out of place. 
The invariable relation in such cases is sufficiently 

:■ established by perception, etc., (of the instances of 
agreement in presence). (Thus the agreement 
in absence is without real usefulness.) Notwith- 

■ : standing this it may be conceded that the agree- 
ment in absence serves some sort of purpose as 

. indicating in a way that the positive relation of 
agreement in presence is not negatived by any 
instances of the failure of the agreement (i.e., by 

; any instances to the contrary.) 

According to another (Nyaya) classification, 
inference is of two kinds, viz., (1) inference for 
oneself, and (2) inference for convincing others. 

t Of these, inference for oneself is the cause of self- 

| conviction and the knowledge one gathers for one's 
g-: own self. ...'., J 

An inference for oneself takes place in the 

|foUowing way. A person in the first place makes\ 

repeated personal observation of the togetherness 

of ' smoke ' and ' fire ' in the oven and other 

^places. From such observation he gathers that' 

there is an invariable relation between ' smoke ' 

and 'fire/ Having gathered the invariable 

relation, when he draws near a 'mountain' and 

^thrown into doubt as to the existence of ' fire- 

the mountain, he notes the trail of smoke 

from the mountain and recollects the 



^v. 



:.:'■■■ 



- -A'-a- 



4- 







80 



MADHVA LOGIC 




invariable relation between 'smoke' and 'fire 
(which he gathered from repeated previous obser 
vation). "When the recollection takes place (t 
'where smoke is, fire also is'), and the saitj 
person draws near the mountain (with the trailin 
smoke), the knowledge at once flashes forth that 
'the mountain yonder has smoke which is an 
invariable concomitant of fire.' Thus does hej 
make an inference for himself. This last step 
(i.e., the knowledge that the mountain possesses 
' smoke ' which is invariably related to ' fire ') is 
called paramars'a or inferential reasoning. From 
this (reasoning process) arises the knowled 
that 'the mountain is on fire.' (The abov$ 
illustrates inference for oneself.) As regard^ 
inference for others, it is a fully-expressed reason- 
ing consisting of five steps which are employed 
to convince others as to the way of inferring 

* fire ' from the (observed) presence of ' smoke^* 
The five steps are :— (1) ' Yonder mountain is 
fire,' (2) 'because it smokes,' (3) 'Whate 
has smoke, is also on fire, just as is the oven* 
(4) 'So is it with this (mountain yonder),' ( 

* therefore it (the mountain) is so (on fire).' B 
all this even a second or third person is ass 
of 'fire' from the knowledge of the pres 
of the established mark or sign thereof ({•«»» 
the sign of 'smoke'). The above five steps i 
called respectively (1) Pratijiia, (2) Hetu, 
Udaharanaffl, (4) Upanayah and (5) Nigamm 




PRAMltfACANDBIKA 81 

Of these pratijna '(the statement of the proposition 
to be proved) consists in the statement of the 
subject of the inference as possessing the proban- 
dum as a property. (In the above inference), 
e.g., the statement ' Yonder mountain is on fire ' 
is the pratijna. (2) The hetu (the ground of the 
inference) is the statement of the mark or sign 
" with a suffix indicative of its instrumentality 
(towards the conclusion), e.g. t the statement 
'because it smokes.' '(3} The drstantah is the 
concrete case in which the invariable relation or 
vyapti is apprehended. It is of two kinds, viz., 
(a) sadharmyadrstantah, and (6) midharmya- 
drstantah. A concrete example in which an 
invariable relation of presence is apprehended 
is called a sadharmyadrstantah, e.g., in the in- 
ference (of fire)_ from smoke, the case of the 
oven. A concrete case in which an agreement 
in absence is apprehended is a vaidharmya- 
dfstantah x e.g., in the same inference from 
'smoke,' the case of the great lake. The 
udaharana is the statement of the concrete case 
or example as exemplifying or illustrating the 
invariable relation of which it is a case in point. 
(The udaharana is thus a statement of a case in 
: point while the drstantah is just the concrete case 
?'■!' and no statement of it as illustrative of the 
; invariable relation.) It is of two kinds, viss,^ 
|; (a) sadharmyodaharanam, and (b) vaidharmyo- 
daharanam. A statement of a concrete example 

m li 



82 



mIdha logic 



w 



*",^a 



illustrating an agreement in presence is if 
sadharmyodaharanam > e.g., the statement 'Whafc| 
ever is smoky, is fiery, just as is the oven.' 
statement of a concrete example illustrating an 
agreement in absence is a vaidharmyodaharamnitfi 
e.g., the statement 'What is not fiery, is not 
smoky, just a&is the great lake/ (4) Upanayah^ 
is the statement of the mark, the invariable! 
relation whereof has been well-established in the 
Concrete example, as existing in the subject of the 
inference. It is also of two kinds according to 
the nature of the concrete example (which 

establishes its invariable relation)* ' Th^t 

mountain yonder has a trailing smoke just as the 
oven' is a case of a sadharmyopanayah. 'The 
mountain is not devoid of smoke like the lake: 
is a- case of a vaidharmyopanayah. (5) Nigt$ 
manam (the conclusion) is the statement of thfe> 
subject '(as characterised by the probandum) as 
proved or demonstrated, e.g., the statement 
* Therefore, yonder mountain is om fire-' 

All this, we hold, is unsound and untenable. 4f| 

there is no scope for the two kinds of vydpti 
invariable relation (in inference), so also there 
no scope for the two kinds of udaharana (illustratl 
ing such relation). Besides, the alleged rule as 
the necessity of five steps in inference is an 
proved assumption. The way in which the 8 
posed necessity of the five steps may be refu 
has been set forth in the Paddhati and the 




■ ■-■ 



' *', 



■■■''. 



§£;' PRAMll?ACANDBIKA : 83 

is referred thereto for an understanding of the 
method of the refutation. This closes our disser- 
tation on the nature of inference. 

We shall now discuss the fallacies of reason- 
ing. The fallacies are of two kinds, viz., (I)' 
fallacies arising from discrepancy or contradiction 
! (virodha), and (2) fallacies of inappropriateness 
(asangati). Of these, the fallacies of contradiction .; 
are of three kinds, viz., contradiction in the 
; pratijM or proposition to be proved, contradiction 
.. in the hetu 01 ground, and contradiction in the ; 
)■- dr§tantah or illustration. Contradiction in the 
*.': pratijM again may be of two kinds, viz., contra- 
: diction of the pratijM or proposition to be proved ;. 
J: with what is established by the recognised source^ J 
I^Vof knowledge, and internal self-contradiction ifrjM 
the proposition in question. Of these again, --con^# 
' tradiction with the evidence of the accepted sources ] : 
% of knowledge may be of two kinds, viz., contradict ^| 

tion with the deliverance of a stronger evidence 
¥■ or proof, and contradiction with the deliverance of 
an evidence of equal strength or force. The follow- 
H -ing is an example of a proposition in contradictioig 

with the deliverance of stronger evidence :— 'The 
j^subject-matter of controversy (i.e., the world) 
is false; because it is an object of perception j 
Whatever is an object of perception, is false, pfc 
as is the silver that is (falsely) perceived iaJWO; 
^shining mother-of-pearl.' . This conch^ /$.•;: 
ieotradicted by the ,e*idence <t £*£!£ MM 



.KiSr> 



. 



=*> 



84 



MADHA LOGIC 



which objects like the jar, etc., are presented 
real, by the evidence of inference also as it proves 
the opposite, viz., * The subject under discussion^ 
(the world) is real, because it yields expected 
results, just as admittedly real things do,' and 
lastly by the evidence of scriptural testimony^ 
which declares the world to be real. It thus J 
runs counter to the combined evidence of percept 
tion, inference and authoritative testimony. 
Hence it is in contradiction with evidence of 
stronger force or strength. As an example of| 
contradiction with evidence of equal force <H?:; 
strength we have the following pair of inferences : 
—(1) ' The disputed subject (i.e., the world) i»:| 
false ; because it is perceptible ; just as is the silver 
perceived in the locus of the mother-of-pearLVJ 
(2) 'The disputed subject (i.e., the world) is real; 
because it is the object of valid knowledge ; josfeS 
as is the self.' In these two inferences, the 
corresponding invariable relations as also the 
presence of the respective grounds in the corres- 
ponding subjects being exactly of the same order, 
we have here a contradiction between evidences 
of equal strength and force. An internally discre- 
pant or self-contradictory statement may, agafliJJ 
be of two kinds. It may be an apasiddhanta 
a jatL An apasiddhanta is an asserted pro] 
tion that contradicts the accepted beliefs of one' 
own school of thought. Since one has subscril 
to the tenets of the school to which one i 




ra. 



PRAMA^ACANDRIKA 85 

elected oneself, in making a statement contradict- 
ing such tenets one is really contradicting oneself. 
This is why an apasiddhdnta is regarded as a 
form of self-contradiction. A statement of the 
existence of God by one belonging to the atheistic 
Sankhya School of thought is an example of this 
kind of self-contradiction. When one refutes 
oneself by the very assertion one makes we have 
that form of self-contradiction which is called 
jati. For example, one who says 'My mother 
is childless ' commits this form of self-contradic- 
tion. Virodha or contradiction in the hetu or 
ground is also of two kinds, viz., svarupdsiddkih 
and avyaptih. The following is an example of 
svarupasiddhih.: — ' Sound is non-eternal, because 
it is visible. ' Here visibility is non-existent in 
sound, sound being audible (and not visible). 
Avyaptih again is of three kinds. We have 
avyaptih when the mark or sign (the ground of 
the inference) is related to the probandum as well 
as the absence of the probandum. iWe have also 
avyaptih where the mark or sign is related to the 
absence of the probandum without being related 
to the probandum. Lastly, we have avyaptih 
where the mark or sign is unrelated both to the 
probandum and the absence of it As an example 
of the first (of these three) we have the follow- 
ing :— f Sound is non-eternal, because it is know- 
able/ The following is an example of the 
second :^-' Sound is eternal, because it is a 



86 



MADHVA LOGIC 




product of will/ As an example of the third 
have : 'All that is, is non-eternal, because 
exists.' In this last example, the subject of tbli 
inference being ? whatsoever that is' the hetu^ 
or ground is unrelated both to the probandu 
and the absence thereof. (Since the subject h 
this case is 'all,' i.e., everything actual 
possible, there is nothing outside the subject 
serve the purpose of a probandum or the abse: 
thereof. Therefore the hetu or ground as 
property of the subject is without relation to 
probandum as well as the negation of it. T 
being no probandum, there is also no absence 
probandum and thus the hetu or ground is wi 
out relation to either.) Contradiction in 
example is of two kinds, viz., contradicti 
arising from the example being without relati 
to the probandum, and contradiction arisi 
from the example being without relation to 
ground. The former is illustrated in the follow 
ing: — 'The mind is non-eternal, because it ha| 
shape, just as the atom has. 5 The second*;*} 
illustrated by the same inference if in place of. 
words 'the atom' we substitute the 
r action.' (We shall now deal with the f 
of inappropriateness.) An example of the £ 
of inappropriateness is addressing to an admitted! 
theist the traditional theistic argument: — *Tfce§ 
earth and the rest have an intelligent 
because they are effects, just as is a piecey 



. L ... - : \\ 






"h 



M 



PBAMAtfACANDRIKl -'W- ' 

cloth.' The inappropriateness consists here in 
the absence of any demand for such an inference 
(the addressee being a theist and therefore not 
standing in need of being convinced). The in- 
appropriate is just that for which there is no 
real need. This is the definition of the inappro* 

priate. - 

Others - (the Naiyayikas) enumerate the fol- 
lowing five as the essential characters of the hetu 
or ground of a valid inference :— (1) existence in 
the subject of the inference as its property or 
Hharma, '(2) existence in the co-ordinates or 
' similar instances, (3) exclusion from the contra-* ; 
ordinates to the inferential subject, i.e., from : 
; . dissimilar instances, (4) non-sublation of its visaya 
§ or object* (5) absence of a counter-feef u or : : ,| 
f' : counter-ground leading to a contradictory conclu- 
sion. Of these, all the five characters are attri- 
buted to the ground of an amayavyatirete-j 
(^inference. The ground of a kevalanvayi inference; :|: 
§ however should possess only four of these^-j 

there being no contra-ordinate or dissimilar 
§ instance in such inference and so the exclusion of -^ 
Ij the ground from the contra-ordinate or dissimilar 
instance being impossible in this case. The 
„ ground of the kevalavyatireki is likewise required 
feto possess only four characters, there being no 
co-ordinate or similar instance in such inferen^g^ 
|bkI therefore existence of the ground in the: 
lidmate.or- similar, instance being <*M4jg 



w 



■A *i - 




•4-2 



fW 



"** 



88 



MlDHVA logic 




-.1- 



■:& 



: -Ki 






- .1 ■ * 

■ r t* 



^ 



yf't I 



question in this case. The fallacious hetu 
ground (according to these Naiydyikas) is 
ground that possesses only some of the abo 
characters and does not possess the rest. T 
fallacious ground is either the asiddha, or t 
viruddha, or the anaikantika, or the kalutyay 
padista, or the satpratipak$a ground or hetu. An 
asiddha or unestablished hetu or ground -is one th 
is devoid either of the character of invariable rela- 
tion (to the probandum) or of the character afg 
being a property of the subject of the inference 
There are three kinds of an asiddha or uflg 
established hetu, viz., an diraydsiddhah hetu, 
smrUpasiddhah hetu and a vtjdpyatvdsiddhah hetu> 
An d&raydsiddhah hetu, i.e., a ground with i 
diraya or substrate unestablished, is of two kin 
mz. r z, ground with an asserted substrate 'that d 
not actually exist, and a ground with an assertftjp 
substrate in which the existence of the 
bandum is admitted as an established fact, 
former is illustrated in the following inference It, 
' The sky-lotus is fragrant, because it is a lot 
just as is the lotus in the lake/ Here 
substrate of the ground is the sky-lotus, 
a sky-lotus nowhere exists. The second 
is illustrated in the case where the 
inference 'The earthy etc., have an intelligent! 
author, because they are effects, Just as r jfej 
piece of cloth ' is employed for the benefit 
convinced theist. Here the probandunbs: 




m 











prama^acandrikI 89 

r 

admitted (before the inference) to be a character 
of the subject, there is no subject in which the 
existence of the probandum is doubted. Thus 
there being no subject to which the probandum 
may be (hypothetical^) attributed for purpose of 
demonstration and proof by means of the in- 
ference, the substrate of the hetu or ground is 
non-existent for logical purposes. (Here the 
subject of the inference is ' the earth, etc,/ and 
this, according to the theist, being admittedly the 
handiwork of God, the proving of the same b 
means of the presence of the ground 
superfluous. Thus the hetu has no logic 
tion with reference to the asserted su 
this is the same as saying that the 
subject is no logical subject, i.e., does 
for logical purposes. The svarupasiddhah 
ground is illustrated in the following : * Sou 
non-eternal, because it is visible.' Here the 
ground is 'visibility/ and this is non-existent 
is sound, sound being audible (and not visible). 
The vyapyatvdsiddhah hetu or ground is of twflK^ 
kinds, viz., a hetu or ground devoid of all relatio&g| 
to the probandum, and a hetu or ground rdateSg* 
to the probandum only through an extraneous 
|c©»dition. The former ia illustrated . in -th^|gg 
^following :— ' All that is, is momentary, becao*#p||| 
^exists/ -Here as the subject of the infei^»^gfe||" 
S»B4 (and thus comprises everything), there WW? "' " 
similar instance or co-ordinate to the subject outside 

12 , : v m 



■£ 





':■,' 



90 



MADHVA LOGIC 



the subject, and therefore the hetu or ground has 
relation to anything outside the subject, i.e., haal 
no relation to the probandum (there being n# 
probandum in reality). The latter is illustrated 
in the following : — ' Vedic sacrifice (of animals) 
is a cause of sin, because it entails destruction of 
life, just as is the killing of a Brahmin.' Efere^ 
' scriptural prohibition * is the extraneous condi^j 
tion through which ' destruction of life ' become*^ 
* productive of sin.' (On condition that the; 
1 destruction of life ' is also one that is prohibited^ 
by scriptures, is it a source of sin. Thus not^ 
' destruction of life * as such, but such ' des 
tion of life ' as is scripturally prohibited, is &| 

source of sin.) (What, then, is an extraneous| 
condition or upadhi ?) An upadhi or extraneous! 
condition is defined as one which pervades thp| 
probandum but does not pervade the ground. 
' Scriptural prohibition ' (in the above inference)^ 
is an extraneous condition in this sense. Tlnl^ 
wherever there is productivity of sin, therfc 
scriptural prohibition may or may not be. Iff 
the subject of the above inference, e.g., (&«*,.!$ 
sacrifice sanctioned by Vedic prescription) there 
is destruction of life but no scriptural prohibition: 
But how, it may be asked, is the presence of 
extraneous condition a defect in reasoning? 
this way, we reply.) The presence of an extra- 
neous condition is a defect as revealing the faita 
of the concomitance (on which the inference 






*::*>. 
a 

»* 



■ ■■'■■ 



&m 



m->:-* 



; fRAMA?TACANl)RIKi 8f ' 

based) or as showing the inference to lead to a 
contradictory conclusion, i.e., as showing forth 
the subject as related not to the probandum 
but to the contradictory of it. For the extraneous 
condition, e.g., scriptural prohibition, being non- 
pervasive of the ground (viz., animal sacrifice), 
may also be excluded from the subject of the 
inference (viz., Vedic sacrifice), and being 
so excluded may effect the exclusion of the 
probandum which it pervades, viz., productivity 
of sin. And so it may show forth the ground* 
viz., 'animal sacrifice/ as being related, not to 
the probandum, but to the contradictory of the 

! probandum. (In other words, it proves the 
failure of the concomitance between the ground 
and the probandum, for as non-pervasive of the 
ground, it shows forth the ground as capable of /■■;■ 
falling outside its range and thereby as failing to 
be related to the probandum which it pervades.) 
For the pervading (i.e., the extraneous condition :,' 
pervading the probandum) being itself non- 

■ pervasive of, i.e., capable of being unrelated to, ••: , 
the ground, the pervaded (i.e., the probandum '% 
which is pervaded by such extraneous condition) ^|| 
must also be similarly capable of being unrelated 
to the ground. And so the subject of the infer- 
ence being shown to be reduced to the position 
of the contraordinate to the subject, the ground 

/asserted to be existing in the subject is shown ta ; 

:be, reduced to the position of a fallacious non- ,..,. 



■■?m 



92 MADHVA LOGIC M® 



&£] 



*m 



';i^a» 



^ ■ 



■W 



invariable ground. Further, the upadhi 
shows forth the subject as related to the cont#i|| 
dictory of the probandum, i.e., it gives rise to an|| 
inference proving a contradictory conclusion, 
the following way. The upadhi or extrane 
condition, being itself excluded from the subj 
of the inference, also effects the exclusion the 
from of the probandum which it pervades, 
thus the absence of the upadhi establishes t 
absence of the probandum. Hence we get t 
counter-inference establishing a contradicto 
conclusion: — 'Vedic sacrifice is not productft&f 
of sin, because it is not prohibited, just as i 
the daily meal.' In this way ' sacrifice of life ' 
is a vyapyatmsiddah hetu or ground, being subj 
to an extraneous condition (in the matter of i 
invariable relation to the probandum). u$)ad 
may be of four different kinds. In the first p 
an upadhi may be an extraneous condition 
vading the probandum without qualification < 
restriction. Secondly, an upadhi may pervade t 
probandum as qualified by a property of 
subject of the inference. Thirdly, an upadhi 
be a condition pervading the probandum as quaJk f 
fied by a property of the ground or sddhana. La 
an upadhi may be a condition pervading the : f|!jfl 
bandum as qualified by a neutral property (**&>:$■ 
property which is neither a property of the subje<S|| 
nor a property of the ground of the inference)*! 
The first of these is illustrated in the i 



■"R*; 






VS 



ssff* 



W;i^y 



PRAMA^ACANDKIKA 



93 



V*'. 



* Yonder mountain is smoky, because it is fiery,' , 
where the presence of greenwood is the upadhi or 
extraneous condition. (Provided the fire is green- 
wood fire, it is a sign of smoke. Thus ' greenwood 
is the condition of the fire being a sign of smoke. 
Now this ' greenwood ' is pervasive of the proban- 
dum 'smoke' without any qualification.) The 
second is illustrated in the following :—' Air is 
perceptible, because it is the substrate of percep- 
tible touch.' Here the upadhi is ' generated colour ' 
which is pervasive of perceptibility in external 
substances. Here ' being an external substance', 
is a property of the subject of the inference, viz.,. ■ 
air. Now 'generated colour' (which is the,:... 
upadhi) does not pervade the probandujn ^ 
(viz., perceptibility) simply without qualification. 
In quality, etc., e.g., there is 'perceptibility/ 
inspite of the absence of 'generated colour.' 
Hence we have to say 'perceptibility in sub- 
stances.' (' Generated colour ' does not pery*dfcp| 
•.perceptibility ' as such, but ' perceptibility itk^ 
external substances.' This excludes ' perceptibility 
of quality, etc' which is not pervaded by 'generated^ 
colour.') But even this does not suffice. The 
Atman or self, e.g., is a perceptible substance, 
perceptibility of the Atman as substance is ^|g| 
pervaded by generated colour. And 
!?have to say, 'perceptibility in external, 
l^wices.' (The Atman ,4f ; not an ^"J*? 
bstance. It is an internal substance revealed 



so we 




?<t: 



. * ~'* 



*'/ ' v \ 



m 



■ : s*t: 



.■.-mm 




94 MADHVA LOGIC •..#■ 

to internal perception.) The third form .^ 
upadhi is illustrated in the following:—'! 
ehild in the mother's womb ought to be a dark- 
coloured one, because it is the child of Maitri.|. 
Here the upadhi is ' vegetable diet/ and it 
pervades 'darkness of colour with respect to 
child of Maim: In this case the tipaihi f \ 
* vegetable diet,' does not pervade the proband^ 
without 'qualification/ In the (unbaked) ja^ 
e.g., there is darkness of colour, but there is no 
'vegetable diet/ Therefore we have to say ' the, 
upadhi pervades darkness of colour as relating fe| 
a child of MaitrV The fourth form is illustrate^ 
in the following :— ' The colour of the atom is 
perceptible, because it is an object of knowledge 
just as is the jar/ Here the upadhi is ' genera 
colour/ and it pervades * perceptibility relating ifl| 
external substances/ Now 'being an ext 
substance ' is a neutral property in this case, 
is not a property of the subject (' the colour * 
the atom'). It is also not a property of the 
ground (* knowability '). Further in this cast| 
we cannot say that ' where perceptibility ;1S^ 
there also generated colour is/ since the con- 
comitance fails in the case of e quality ' and tb^ 
like. Hence 'generated colour' is not pervasi*6; 
of the probandum (i.e., perceptibility) simplj 
without qualification. Hence we say 
ceptibility relating to external substances 1 . 
the meaning is ' where perceptibility relating 



■■-■■ 



».•>■ 



V-* 



prama^acandrik! 95 

external substances is, there generated colour 
also is,' and in this respect the upadhi, ' generated 
colour/ pervades the probandum, ' perceptibility \ 
But this upadhi, 'generated colour/ does not 
pervade the ground, ' knowability \ We cannot 
say ' whatever is knowable, is also characterised 
by generated colour/ the concomitance being seen 
to fail in the case of the subject of the inference 
(the colour of the atom). (The colour of the 
atom is knowable, but it is non-generated colour.) 
If we define upadhi merely as a condition that 
does not pervade the ground (and leave out the 
other part of the definition, i.e., that such condition 
must also be pervasive of the probandum), then 
in the inference ' sound is non-eternal, because 
it is a product of will' the property of ' being a 
jar ' will be. an upadhi, for in a sound which is 
a product of will, there is absence of the property 
of a jar. (But the above inference is free from an 
upadhi, and therefore our mutilated definition of 
upadhi is the cause of the illegitimate assumption 
of an upadhi in this case.) Again if we define 
upadhi simply as a condition that pervades the 
probandum (omitting the other part of the defini- 
tion that 'it must be non-pervasive of theground'), 
then in the inference of - fire ' from * smoke/ ' the 
nature of being a substance ' will be an upadhi. 
(Fire is a substance and therefore pervaded 
by 'the nature of being St substance'.) There- 
tore (to avoid the absurdity of supposing an 



^v* 



96 



MADHA LOGIC 



:w 







«padfei where there is none) we say * the tfpadhi:^ 
must also be non-pervasive of the ground,; 
(The nature of being a substance perv 
* smoke ' also and thus is not non-pervasive 
the ground.) The viruddhah heta, i.e., t 
contradictory ground, is one that is pervaded 
the negation of the probandum. E.g., the grou0j| 
in the inference 'sound is eternal, because it is if 
product of will/ is a contradictory or viruddha 
ground. The ground in this inference is 'being 
product of will/ and 'being a product of will' 
pervaded by 'non-eternality' which is the negation 
of 'eternality/ The anaikantikah hetu or gro 
is one that is non-invariable (i.e., one which 
not invariably related to the probandum). 
anaikdntika ground is of three kinds, viz., the g 
sadharana or common, the asadharana or 
common and the anupasathhdri or inconclusive 
Of these the sddhdranah anaikantikah is a gro 
that exists also in that which is a negation of 
probandum. (It is common to the proba 
and its negation and therefore is called sad 
anaikdntika or common non-invariable.) 
ground in the inference 'the mountain is on 
because it is knowable' is an example of this 
of a non-invariable ground. The ground in 
case is 'being a knowable* and this holds 
also of the lake which is devoid of fire. 
uncommon anaikdntika is a ground^ that 
excluded from all co-ordinates and contra-ordi 





Hal 







?*>?.; A 



pramI^tacandrika 



97 



to the subject and exists only in the subject. 

?': For example, the ground in the inference 'the 
element of earth is eternal, because it has odour * 

f is a case of an uncommon non-invariable ground. 
Here 'possession of odour' which is the ground or 
hetu exists only in the subject of the inference, 
viz., in the element of earth, and is excluded alike 
from all other eternal and non-eternal objects. 
The inconclusive anaikmtika is a ground which 
'is bereft alike of instances showing its agreement 
in presence with the probandnm. and instances ., 
showing its agreement in absence therewith. For 
example, the ground in the inference 'All that 
m, is non-external, because it is knowable ' is a 
-case of an inconclusive non-invariable ground. 
Here the subject of the inference being 'all *l*gi 

* is* there is nothing outside the subject to serve as 

-an illustration of the invariable relation between 

the ground and the probandnm. The kalMyaya- 

t ; padista hetu or ground is one that seeks ^YjMg 
a probandnm the negation of which is established 
by valid evidence to be the property of the subject. 



mblated 

ground 



1 



following inference is a case in point :— Fire is 
devoid of heat, because it is knowable/ Here 
the probandnm is 'absence of heat but tfie 
Rogation of this probandnm, viz., 'heat, is proved 
by tactual perception to be the property of fire 
which is the subject of the inference. The 



v- -V' 



& 



P 

plfccY.13 




98 MADHVA LOGIC 

satpratipaksa hetn or ground is one which has a 
counter-ground opposed to it proving the negation 0| 
of the probandum (in the subject of the inference). i$ 
For example, the ground of the inference 'sound 
is eternal, because it is audible, just as is the 
class-character or generic nature of sounds' is 
countered and stopped from functioning by the 
ground of the inference 'sound is non-eternal, 
because it is an effect, just as is the jar/ A ; 
countered or hindered ground is also called a , ■ 
prakaranasamafy hetu. t K 

Just as we have the fallacious ground or . : > 
pseudo-ground (in various forms) so also we have ^ 
the fallacies of the example or ud&harana, i.e., ..." 
fallacious examples or pseudo-examples (udaharana- 
bhasah). There are many different kinds of the 
fallacious example. For example, with reference 
to examples illustrating relations of agreement in 
presence, we have first the case of a fallacious .- 
example which is bereft of relation to the * ■• 
probandum. Thus in the inference 'the mind is ■ 
non-eternal, because it has shape; whatever has , 
shape, is non-eternal; just as is the atom,' the ^ 
'atom* which is cited as illustrating the agree- ^ 
ment in presence is a pseudo-example in this sense. 
For the atom i3 devoid of 'non-eternality' and so 
is devoid of relation to the probandum. Secondly, 
we may also have pseudo-examples that are bereft 
of relation to the ground. In the same inference 
if we say 'just as is action ' (in place of * just 



:-,r 






..» 



it. 



PRAMAtfACANDBlfcA 99 



■ V 

as is the atom') we shall have a pseudo-example 

bereft of relation to the ground, for action, though 

non-eternal, is yet devoid of * shape.' And 

thirdly, we may also have fallacious examples 

which are bereft of relation both to the ground 

and the probandum, e.g., in the same inference, 

if we say ' just as is ether ' (in place of ' just 

as is the atom') we shall have a pseudo-example 

devoid of relation to the ground as well as the 

probandum. (Ether is devoid of shape and is 

devoid of non-eternality.) In the case of examples 

illustrating relations of agreement in absence, we 

may also have pseudo-examples devoid of relation 

to the absence of the probandum. For example, in 

.the same inference if we say ' just as is action (by 

agreement in absence).' (Action is non-etemal 

and therefore is devoid of relation to the negation 

or absence of non-eternality.) Secondly, we may 

also have in such cases fallacious examples in the 

form of examples bereft of relation to the absence of 

the ground. For example in the same inference, if 

we say ' what is not non-eternal, is not an object 

with a shape, just as is the atom.' And 

lastly, we may have also fallacious examples 

; bereft of relation both to the absence of the 

ground and the absence of the probandum. For 

example, in the same inference, if we say 

• 'just as is the jar.' (The jar is non-eternal 

if and therefore bereft of relation to the negation 

feflf non-eternality. The jar further has a shape 



:>5 V 

si 



*-£» 






:?* 



:-- 



100 MlDHVA LOGIC 

and is therefore bereft of relation to the negation 
of shape.) 

All these (i.e., the Nyaya fallacies so far set 
forth) we reject as untenable. Why ? Because^ 
some of these so-called fallacies are not fallacies? 
strictly speaking, while the rest are comprehended 
in 'conflicting evidence * and the other fallacies weg| 

have explained above. 

The manner in which some of these so-called 
fallacies may be proved to be logically flawless as : ^ 
also the manner in which the rest may be showa,1| 
to be comprehended in our enumerations of the ^ 
fallacies are fully set forth in the PaddhaU ioj& 
which the reader is referred for an understanding;!^ 
thereof. We refrain from going over the same , 
ground here for fear of prolixity. Thus every-|| 
thing (relating to inference) has been correctl|||| 
and intelligibly set forth. This closes the chapte£j| 
on Anumana of the Pramanacandrika which 
follows the track shown by the reverend feet-<$J)g 
Sri Jayatlrtha. Let our heads bend in honour to|p 
the sage Vedavyasa and let us close with an i*£ : l| 
vocation of the name of Hari and the incantation 
of Om. 

We now proceed to discuss the nature of 
Authority or Agama as a source of knowledge 
Any verbal communication free from defects b 
Sgama. The qualification *free from defects' 
■ (in the above definition) distinguishes agama h 
the mere (deceptive) appearance thereof, 



W- : . : - ■ ■-■■■ 








PRAMA^ACAMDMKA 101 

Hie words 'verbal communication' differentiate it 

from perception and other sources of knowledge. 
'&.'. What, then, are the defects of a verbal 
^jporamunication? The defects of a verbal commu- 
nication are :-(D unintelligibility, (2) conveying 
of the opposite of the true or correct information,, 
? (3) conveying of what is already known, (4) con- 
veying of "useless information (for which nobody 
cares), (5) conveying of information not derived, 
:, or sought for by the person to whom it is con- 
veyed, (6) conveying of a command or injunction, 
to accomplish the impossible, (7) conveying of 
advice of a more difficult means when easier means 
I are well within reach, etc. Of these (1) umntelli-, 

gibility is of two kinds, viz., (a) unintelligibly. ; , 
I due to want of significant words, and (6) un-r.^ 

intelligibility due to want of intelligible relation 
: ; : (between the words of a verbal communication).. 
Examples of the former are : -'Because ka^a-ta- .,.. 
ta-pc'B are ja-ba-ga-da-ha' (of. abracadabra). 
Examples of the latter are :-'The cow M^ga 
P f horse,"Manisan elephant,' 'The bowl.rr%g| 
'i cumin seed,' ' The ten apples are five cakes. U) 
Conveying the opposite of what is true is illus- 
trated in the following : -'The world is unrea^| 
I: ' The Sudras have the right of access to the, 
IfeVedas,' 'The Brahmins have no such right, etc. 
' £&. Examples of conveying what is already k«^||J 
«e :-« The sun rises in the east, and sets gJSg? 
-—*!-. < u.i AMUH .» » WR et * 'The Nimbajr^rt :»/.■■ -> s 




* 



w-^ 



■a 






102 MADHVA LOGIC 

bitter,' etc. The objection that 'conveying thfc 
known cannot be a defect as it adds to the forced 
of the evidence that is already available (and thus 
strengthens our knowledge), misses the real point 
at issue. Later evidence strengthens our know- 
ledge only where earlier evidence has failed to 
remove uncertainty and produce complete certitude 
in regard to that about which we were in doubt. 
(Hence where no uncertainty exists, the attempt at 
further enlightenment by means of verbal commu- 
nication is waste of energy.) (4) Examples of 
stupid, pointless communications (for which 
nobody cares) are :•— ' How many teeth has the 
crow ? ' ' What is the weight of the sheep's 
egg ? * ' How many threads of hair are there ,';| 
in the blanket?' ' What is the news of the province 
of Cola? ' (Gola being the name of the place where - : S 
the questioner himself lives), etc. (5) Examples p 
of communications which are of no use to the*.;/ 
persons to whom they are conveyed are : — c Advice v;I 
of business and trade to one who has subdued 
the desires of the world,' etc. (6) Examples of 
communications enjoining the accomplishment of 
the impossible are : — ' When alluding to a person 
who is dead and gone, one proceeds to describe an 
elixir that will bring the dead back to life and 
that may be found in the north of a certain hiHl 
called Mrtiharamahtdhara,* etc. (7) Examp 
advising more difficult and less accessible remedi 
where easier ones are at hand are : — * To ask 









# 




'£ 



PRAMA^ACANDRIKA 



103 



man to cut down something with an axe which 
he can easily remove by his finger-nails,' 'To 
advise a thirsty man on the Ganges banks to sink 
a well for quelling his thirst,' etc. 

A verbal communication is made up of words 
and sentences. A word is a combination of 
letters with a case-ending. The words 'with 
a case-ending ' (in the above definition) exclude 
non-sense combinations of letters like ja-ba- 
ga-da-ia (which are devoid of case-endings). A 
sentence is a combination of words characterised 
by mutual expectation, suitability of relation, and 
proximity (in time) . Expectation is that relation 

" of one word of a sentence to another (or others) 
of the same sentence without which the relation 
expressed by the sentence will not be apprehended, 
e.g., in the sentence ' Bring the jar,' the verb 
('bring') without the object ('jar') will not 
produce the apprehension of the relation of a 
verb to its object, and so the verb ' bring' has the 
relation of expectation to the object ' jar ' . Or we 
may say, expectation is the fulfilling (on the part 
of the subsequest word) of the intent or expecta- 
tion which is generated by the word preceding it 

. (in a sentence). Therefore, 'The cow is a 
horse,' ' Man is an elephant,' etc, are not 
sentences, for in these the words do not expect 

: ; i.e., enter into relation to, one another. Though 

/^'expectation' is, strictly speaking a property of 
consciousness, yet objects .(denoted by words), 



n\ 




* 

104 " MADHA LOGIC 

as producing in the bearers of their respecti 
names an expectation of these objects in mut 
relation, are also said to * expect * one ano 
And as words (the names of objects) denote su 
objects (with mutual expectation), words also a 
said to have ' expectation.' 

By suitability or fitness of relation (bet 

the words of a sentence) is meant the absence iif^ 
the cognised relation (between the said words) of?; 
any clash with valid evidence. Thus in the words 
'moistening by water/ the relation of effect and! 
cause which is asserted between the act 
* moistening ' and the agency of ' water ' remaiM 
uncontradicted by valid evidence. Here the coBff^ 
patibility of the relation between 'moistening' 
and the agency of * water * constitutes the s 
lity or fitness of the relation between them. F 
this reason the words, 'He is moistening 
means of fire,' do not constitute a real sen 
there being no suitability of relation in this 
Between 'fire' and the act of 'moistening 
there is no question of a mutual agreement^ 
compatibility of relation. 

By proximity (in time) is meant the express- 1| 
ing of the words (in a sentence) without -aBj;|j 
long pause or interval of time between the 
ferent words. Thus the words, '■ Bring the 
uttered without any long break or interval' 
time between them, have this character 
proximity (in time) . For this reason* -tfeR 





PRAMA^ACANDRIKA 105 

■ ' Bring the cow/ uttered separately, each after an 
hour or thereabout after the previous one, will 
not constitute a sentence, for they lack the 
character of sufficient (temporal) proximity (to 
produce a unity of meaning). 

In verbal communication as a source of 
knowledge, the sentence is the instrumental 
cause, the recollection of the meanings of 
the constituent words, the intervening process, 
and the knowledge of the meaning of the 
sentence, the result (of the process). 
Verbal communication also (like inference) 
conveys knowledge only of such correctly Com- 
municated objects as are accompanied by the 
knowledge of the meanings of the constituent 
words of the communication. In this respect it 
is unlike perception (as an instrument of know- 
ledge) which makes things known by its 
bare existence (without being itself known 
or apprehended), for an authoritative commu- 
nication like inference depends on a known 
instrumental cause (i.e., the knowledge of the 
meanings of its constituent words). Otherwise 
the absurdity will follow that an authoritative 
v knowledge will have to be admitted where a 
verbal declaration (of a truth), though existing 
k in itself, has not been actually heard by a parti- 
:{ : cular person, or, even though heard by him, 
5 has not been understood because of lack of know- 
ledge of the meanings of the constituent words. 

§•'• 14. 



106 



MADHVA LOGIC 




(We now proceed to discuss how words mi 
tteir respective objects.) Some hold that woi 
like 'the cow,' etc., mean only class-characters, 
these being the first to be presented as attribul 
(as soon as the words are heard). The individuals 
are reached (mediately) through these class- 
characters which drag them behind themselves. 
Others hold that words mean the individuals 
as specified by their corresponding class-charao^ 
ters. According to this view, a class-name is 
subject to the conditions which regulate the use 

^ok words. Thus all words such as ' ether/ etc.^ 
mean specified individuals, these alone being thftf 
determining conditions of the use of words. 
Otters' hold that words like £ the jar,* etc., meatt 
class-characters; proper names like * Devadatta,' 
etc., mean individuals ; words like ' possession 

/. the "dewlap* mean shape or make; while words 
like * the cow,' etc., mean all the three. The real 

> fac£ however, is that the meaning of a wordil 

' jusf "{fiat object which is immediately presented^ 
to consciousness as soon as the word is heara-i 
Tn the apprehension of the meaning of a w< 
similarity acts as connecting or mediating link- 
Thus since the word 'jar' calls forth the i<k 
both of c individual jars * and ' the , class-characte||J 
of jars,' this word must be supposed to be cap) 
of meaning both the ( class-character T and ' thi 
individuals.' Again, since the word ' white ' * 
forth the idea of the quality of white <$$% 



V 



^ * l n 



-♦.-V'.-ry-: 



i~ , :** 



SB 





prama^taoandmka , '*■ ifft c 

P well as the substrate of the quality (the white 
pithing), it must be supposed to mean both ' the 
quality ' and ' the substrate.' Similarly, the word 
H 'gone' means both the action of ' having gone ' 
W and ' the agent of the action,' the word 'stick-. 
# in-hand' means both the 'stick' and 'the 
^person, Devadatta, who holds it in his hand,' etc. 
i. Or, we may say, words like 'cow' etc., being 
5 nouns or substantives, must denote individuals, 
while words like ' bring,' etc., should mean attri- 
butes or adjectives. .In combinations of words 
| such as 'bring the cow,' the act of bringing 
being made possible through an individual 
'■: agent of the act, the meaning should be conceived ■'■.]. 
v.; as consisting in the individual (in the individual -i j ^ 

f agent of the act) . '"'"' , '■';■/% 

T'- (The question now has to be discussed, how 3 
SPwe acquire a knowledge of the meanings of 
p words.) Our view is that we learn the meanings 
foof words from the signs made with the fingers 
T" (by our elders while uttering the words). Thus 
!; the child sitting on the person of its father or 
l-mother begins to learn the meanings of wmgg 
I- when the said father or mother tries to rouse '$g| 

from a state of inattention and to draw its atten- 
tion towards himself or her^a^J «*gp 
i words which he or she may uttef^ by' mabn|j|= 

signs with the fingers, or by producing * 
feoft sound by Striking one finger-tip against * 

"another- In this waj^be «hild is taught the v 





ri=v 





■ 'w 

■ 






♦.* 



108 MADHVA LOGIC 

i 

meanings of such sentences as 'Child, that 
is your mother/ 'that, your father, 1 ' that* 
your brother,' 'the man is eating the plantain 
fruit,' etc. Thus by the said signs the child 
gradually learns that the said words are related 
in a general way to the said objects pointed^; 
out by these gestures and that the relational 
is the relation of meaning or signifying these 
objects. Later on when such words as ' This is 

4 

your sister/ 'That is your friend/ 'He is 
eating a cake/ etc., are uttered in his presence, 
and he begins to note the different contexts in. is 

.-.■83 

which these different words are uttered, he 
learns, through the differences of the contexts 

"•'MS 

to distinguish the specific meanings that attach || 
to particular words, e.g., that the word 'mother' 
attaches to 'the female parent,' etc. Otherof" 
however opine that the meanings of words are<s 
learnt from the behaviour of the seniors or elders. 
Thus the inquisitive child, when he hears a senior 
say to a junior, ' Bring the cow/ and notes that? 
immediately afterwords the junior is prompted^ 
to the act of bringing the cow, concludes t$ 
agreement and difference that the action of the 
junior is prompted by the knowledge produce^ 
by the words of the senior. And so assuring! 
himself, when he hears other sentences spo 
in other contexts such as 'Bring the hor 
'Secure the cow with a rope/ etc., he ga 
from the divergent contexts that the 



* 



<<#£*& 



PRAMAJjTACANDRlKA i 109 

' cow ' means one particular kind of animal, the 
word ' horse,' animal of a different kind, etc. But 
this view is not tenable. The quickly-forgetful 
child cannot possibly retain the consciousness of 
the word he hears till the actual bringing of the 

object desired. 

A word has two kinds of function or vrtti, viz., 
(1) primary (mukhya) and (2) non-primary or 
secondary (amukhya). The direct or primary 
function of a word is its iakti or power of 
referring to, or meaning, a particular object. 
Sakti is defined as that relation between a word 
and an object which is conducive to the recollec- 
tion of the object (as soon as the word is heard) . 
Samaya, sangati, sanketa, vacaka, etc., are used 
as synonyms of sakii. This iakti is of three 
kinds, viz., yogah, rtMmA yogarudhih. Of 
these, the power to refer to an object by virtue 
of the powers of the constituent parts of the 
. word is yogah. The power of meaning which 
- belongs to a word as a whole irrespective of the 
powers of its constituent parts is ru4hih. Lastly, 
the power of meaning which is derived from 
both (i.e., both from the word as a whole and 
the meanings of the constituent parts), is yoga- 
ruMh. Of these, some words mean their 
respective objects through the meanings of its 
H. "constituent parts only, such as the words pdthaka 
■'< (reader), pacaka (cook), dan& (the man with a 
I a stick in hand), kun4all {the coiling thing), etc. 



■jM 



110 



MADHVA LOGIC 



PW 



■ ■?:: 



Some words, again, mean their respective object* 
by the powers inherent in the words as a whol 
irrespective of the powers of the constituents, 
Such are words like ghata (jar), pata (piece 
cloth), etc. Lastly, some words mean objec 
through their powers as a whole as reinforced by| 
the powers of the constituents such as the word| 
pankaja (the lotus), etc. In this manner att'g 
other words with primary meanings, such as thef 
mahayogafr, etc., should be understood (as signi- 
fying their objects). 

The non-primary or secondary function of a^ 
word is called Laksana or Implication. Implica- 
tion is a kind of relation to the object of a word's! 

&akt% or power of meaning. There are two kin 
of Implication, viz., (1) Implication which is in* 
dependent of relation to the direct meani 
(Jahallaksana) , and (2) Implication in whioK| 
the direct meaning also enters as a facte 
(ajahallakfana). * The milkman lives in 
Ganges ' illustrates the former. (Here ' the! 
Ganges ' means not the river, but the banks 
the river Ganges.) ' Men with umbrellas 
going* illustrates the latter. (Here chatriti 
i.e. 9 'men with umbrellas,' means * pedestrian®. 
According to another classification, Implicat 
is of the following two kinds, viz., (1) Impli 
tion in which the implied meaning is ij 
dependent of any special end or purpose to 
subserved, and (2) Implication depending <& 



-■-.■. 



■I s 




L#l : 



.*■■■ *. 



prama^tacandrikI 111 



some purpose that is subserved. "' Travellers are 

going' is an example of the former. (Here 

I'm&rgaht literally 'roads,' means 'travellers' 

by implication.) Here the traversing of the 

• roads by travellers being observed to happen 

without any special end or purpose to be served, 

* ,: such implication is also called mjhalakma. 

'The milkman lives in the Ganges' is an example 

of the latter. (Here ' the Ganges ' means ' the 

banks of the Ganges.') In this case ' living near 

the Ganges' being prompted by considerations 

of sanctity and the like, the implication is called 

kevalalak?ana. The inapplicability or failure of 

the primary meaning is the real cause of an 

implication. In a similar way should be con- 

f ceived other non-primary functions of words such 

"/'as the gaunt (the deferred), etc. ,';.,; 

" A~gama, i.e., an authoritative verbal communi- 

: cation is of two kinds, viz., (1) communication 

having a personal source, and (2) communication 

IS devoid of a personal source. The Rg-veda and 

:> other ; orthodox scriptures are the impersonal 

k&gamas, or Agamas without a personal source. 

^ Valid personal communications are those recorded 

>in"'the Mahabharata and other sacred works. 

> v Thus, it is said, " Scriptures are of two kinds,; 

|V viz., (1) the eternal, and (2) the non-eternal. 

Such, for example, are the Vedas beginning with 

Rg-vefa the MahSbharata, the Paflcaratra, the 

original Ramayana, and. the Puxanas. AH these 



.Vi 









i>3 




,« 



112 MADHVA LOGIC 

as also all those that follow in • the wake of tliesii 
are to be regarded as the (authoritative) sacre^l 
scriptures. Those that are other than these. : 
Janatdana, they are heretical and should not 
be regarded as authoritative scriptures, etc." ; .1 

But it may be said : * The Vedas have 1^ 
personal source, because they consist of collections 
of sentences, just as are the verses of Kalidasa r 
and the rest.' Our reply is, this conclusion does v 
not follow, the inference in question being 
vitiated by the presence of an extraneous condK :■■ 
tion. The extraneous condition is ' a personal 
origin established by tradition/ In other words, 
€ a collection of sentences ' (which is the ground 
of the inference) is in itself no proof of a personal 
origin. It is a sign thereof only on the condi- 
tion that such personal origin is established by 
tradition. 

But it may be said : ' The Vedas are devoid of 
evidential value and validity, because despite the 
due accomplishment of the Vedic prescriptions 
the promised fruits are not realised, just as 
are the hopes generated by the utterances of;^| 
deceitful people.' Our reply is, this is not the 
case, because the above inference contradicts the 
following valid reasoning: — 'The Vedas are 
authoritative, because they consist of imperso 
prescriptions, i.e., of sentences without a perso: 
origin, just as are the lunatic's ravings by a 
ment in absence.' (The lunatic's ravings 



^ 

$ 



-■ 




PRAMA^ACANDRIKA 113 

non-authoritative, and they are not without a 
personal source. And thus they illustrate the 
agreement in absence ' what is not authorita- 
tive is also not without a personal source.') 
It cannot be said that this inference entails 
the fallacy of an asiddha hetu or unestablished 
ground. For Sruti (authoritative scripture) 
declares that the sentences of the Vedas 
(i.e., the Vedic prescriptions) are eternal verities. 
(Thus the eternity, i.e., lack of a personal 
origin, in respect of the Vedic sentences, 
is not asiddha or unestablished.) Smjii (i.e., 
the secondary scriptures derived from the 
primary scriptures) also declares that the Vedic 
sentences are without beginning and without 
end, are eternal or timeless, have inherent 
authority and are self-existent. Nor is non- 
fruitfulness or non-efficacy of Vedic prescriptions 
a proof of invalidity (of the Vedas), for the pres- 
criptions being seen to bear the promised fruits 
only in the properly qualified agents accomplish- 
ing them, the non-perception of the fruits in 
other cases must be attributed to the inherent 
disqualifications of the agents. . 

But it may be said : * Agama is not valid 
u., evidence, bacause it does not prove anything, just 
I as a deceitful utterance.' Thus the visaya or 
I;; object to be proved by valid evidence is of two 
fjdn&s, viz., (1) the immediate, and (2) the 
emote nr mediate. Of these, the immediate is 



remote or mediate, ui *« 

m; . 15 



:*-„■■ 



Ua 



1X4 



MADHVA LOGIC 



f?ft 



the object evidenced by perception. There is no 
other object, besides these two, which can servel 
as an object to be established by the evidence rf| 
Kgama or authoritative communication. If you 
say that Agama causes the knowledge of the 
mediate, then as, in your view, nothing is, valid ":|| 
independent evidence which causes the knowledge 
of the already known, and Agama has application 
only to objects proved by other forms of evidence, 
so all Kqamas will be shorn of evidential value aft|!| 

""2* 

wanting in any distinctive objects to be proved^ 
thereby. All this, we reply, is wrong. Just as 
the evidential value of visual perception in regard 
to objects distinct from the objects of hearing 
cannot be denied in spite of the fact t 
visual perception proves only immediate obje 
. just as hearing does, so also the evidence 
Kgama in regard to objects distinct from t 
objects of inference, e.g., in regard to s 
special objects as heavenly happiness, libera 
etc. (which are not objects of inference), ; ii 
unimpeachable despite the fact that Kgama ■ 
indistinguishable from inference in the matt~* 
of the mediateness of the objects it proves. If| 
cannot be said that * heavenly happiness, 
'liberation/ etc., are objects of inferential pr^® 8 
and so Agama is devoid of any special objects' "ttf 
be established by its evidence. For if you s|§ 
this, we shall say contrary wise that Kg 



m 



m 



&2fiM 



being evidence of mediate : objects (sue 






4v. PRAMA^ACANDRIKi .115 

'heavenly happiness,' etc.) is a valid source 
of knowledge, while inference, being devoid of 
proper special objects (i.e., objects not charac- 
terised by the mediateness that characterises the 
objects proved by Igama) is devoid of evidential 

authority. 

The Vawesikas hold that Igama is included 
in (i.e., is a variety of) inference. But this 
view is wrong, for even in the absence of the 
recollection of invariable concomitance and the 
like, there is realisation of the meaning of a 
verbal communication, this being a matter of 
common experience. 

Bhaskara and his followers hold that Agama 
without a personal source is independent evidence, 
but Agama having a personal origin is a variety .g- 
of inference. This also is a wrong view. For the 
sum of conditions for the comprehension of $*^ 
import of sentences, viz., expectancy, suitability 
of mutual relation between the constituent words, 
etc., being identical in both (i.e., both Personal 
and Impersonal Igama), there is no valid ground^ 
for assuming any special character attaching to J g| 

only one of these. ... _■....'-■■- '•'.■■ •■ •• .•'• : sS 
Thus have we described all the three forms 

of evidence or Pramana. Anything other than 
these (three) is not a'prdmSm or valid source- /<4jj| 

: knowledge. - •■-" ■■ ••-:-' '-'' .''*j& : ?i'- 

But it may be said: there is another form 
rf avid*™* distinct from the above three, tnz., 



01 evidence tnswuo- 






■■■ m 

116 mIdhVa logic 

Arthapatti or Presumption. When a thing of% 
event is seen to be inexplicable except on the & 
assumption of something else and when on the , 
basis of our observation of this otherwise inexpH*yf| 
cable thing we are led to presume that which is T| 
necessary to account for it, we proceed according $ 
to the method of Arthapatti or Presumption as 
a source of knowledge. Thus when we learn v 
by perception or reliable testimony that Caitra j> 
is alive and yet is not in the house, we at once ..-| 
presume that he must be somewhere outside, for ;■; 
absence inside of one who is alive is not ;■% 
explicable except on the assumption of his i 
existence outside. Hence the proof here of outside 
existence consists in the Arthapatti or Presume ^ 

tion which is created therefor by the otherwise :| 
inexplicable fact of inside non-existence of one ^ 
who is alive. This process is distinct from the -^ 
processes of perception and the rest, for outside 
existence is not an object of perception and the 

-test. • " ; : 

This, we hold, is not the case, for the «v?| 
called presumption is only an inference '&&$$ 
disguise). (The inference is as follows: %j. 
* Caitra must exist outside, because, though alive, 
he is absent inside ; whoever is alive, and 
does not exist in a certain place, must exist in 

— m + 

some other place, just as I myself do. 
inference being quite competent to produce 
knowledge of the outside existence, whati#| 



Til 

H 

«4 ■ I 

" 41 " 

I 



cVl 



PRAM A?A C AKDBIK A 



11? 



use of assuming a separate source of knowledge 
such as Presumption? In this inference the 
words 'though living' preclude the case of the 
dead (who are non-existent because not alive). 
Similarly, the substantive (qualified by the 
adjective ' though alive '), i.e., 'absence inside,' 
precludes the case of Devadatta and the like 
who are existent within the house. 

But it may be said : there is another separate 
source of knowledge, viz. , comparison. Compari- 
son ( Upamana) is the cognition of an object as 
characterised by likeness to another, e.g., of likeness 
to the cow as produced by the recollection of a 
comparative statement as an auxiliary condition. 
Thus a person ignorant of the meaning of the 
word ' gavaya ' first learns from a forester that 
'gavaya* means ' an animal resembling a cow.' 
Thereafter when later on he comes across in a 
jforest an animal looking like a cow, he recollects 
the previous advice of the forester that ' gavaya 
is an animal like a cow. ' Thereon the knowledge 
dawns on him * That animal (resembling the cow) 
must be what is meant by the word gavaya.' 
As this knowledge is not caused by perception 
and the rest, the process (which generates the 
' knowledge) is regarded as an independent source 
. of knowledge called Upamana or comparison. 

This, we hold, is not the case, for (the so- 
;• called) comparison is really comprised in m- 
i^ Terence. The inference in such cases is as 



MI 



118 MADHVA LOGIC 






follows:— ' The subject of the enquiry is t&| 
meaning of the word gavaya, because, not 
being a cow, it possesses resemblance to a cow| 
just as is the jar by agreement in absence.* 
. (What is not the meaning of gavaya, is also noil 
that which, not being a cow, bears resemblance 

* to the cow, just as is the jar which is not the;|| 
meaning of gavaya and is also not that which,|| 
not being a cow, bears resemblance to tbe|| 
cow.) To preclude illegitimate application to a v| 
second cow resembling a first cow, the words j 

',.* *not being a cow' have been included, and to : 
preclude illegitimate application to the jar an<| 
the rest, the substantive 'that which bears 
resemblance to the cow ' has been included. 

But it may be said: there is yet anoth* 
separate source of knowledge, viz., negation^ 
Abhava. This must be admitted in order 
account for the cognition of negation. ^ln^ 
non-apprehension (i.e., negation or absence of 
apprehension) of the jar and the rest assures; 
us of the absence or negation of the jar, etc.; 
* This non-apprehension is just the negation or 
absence of apprehension. The non-apprehensioiiu 
being apprehended or realised in consciousness* 
the negation, i.e., the absence, of the jar, etc., 
is also cognised or apprehended. 

This is not the case, we say; for this 
called negation as a source of knowledge is 
reality comprehended in one or other <>t. 



.--:■ 



i **■*■■ to 



»X t 



ffe% ■-" PRAMAKACANDRIKA ..' ''''' 119 



■y t ' ' 



w- 



v ■ 



Pramanas we have explained above. Thus, 
according to our view, that which causes the 
knowledge of negation (in a particular case) is 
the Pramana or evidence of the negation in that 
case. For example, the evidence in regard to the 
present non-existence of the Kauravas is the 
testimony of the Mahabharata. In the case of 
Devadatta's lack of vision we have the following 
inference as proof or evidence of the lack or 
negation :— The subject of controversy (Deva- 
datta) is devoid of vision, because he is ignorant 
of the nature of colours.' Similarly, the absence 
of pleasure, etc., is evidenced by the immediate 
intuition of the witnessing intelligence. The 
realisation of the non-existence of a jar before 
oneself results from a quickly-produced percep- 
tion. It is not an effect of non-apprehension 
only, for it has the nature of an immediate 
positive experience. No doubt, a proximate 
non-apprehension is also an indispensable 
condition. But the mere fact of a proximate 
non-apprehension as an indispensable condition 
does not constitute the latter an independent 
source of knowledge, for in that case by a similar 
line of reasoning one may say that in the cogni- 
tion of positive reality the non-apprehension of 
its negation is the real evidence or proof. 
? Where in the midst of darkness we cognise the 
absence of a jar and the like by means of ex- 
ploring with the hands, the non-apprehension 







120 MADHVA LOGIC 

qua non-apprehension is not the real cause of* 
our knowledge of the negation or absence. Thejl 
non-apprehension is a cause here only as itia 1 
treated as a sign or mark serving as the ground 
of an inference. The inference in such cases is *: 
as follows: — 'The jar does not exist here, for, f 
though fit to be perceived, it is not actually ■ 
observed here, just as an elephant.' But it may 
be said : a negation or absence being admittedly v 
incapable of positively stimulating the sensibili- ■] 
ties, we cannot sensibly talk of negation being 
perceived by the -senses. Our reply is : this is •., 
not the case as there is no bar to a negation ;.: 
being in contact with the sensibilites just as there j 
is none with respect to a positive entity. : .^ \ 

But it may be said : we have mathematical -| 
or quantitative reasonings (sambhava) and these ; ! 
should constitute a separate source of knowledge, i 
Thus when the cognition of the greater leads to 
the cognition of the less we have sambhava or 
quantitative reasoning. , For example, the 
knowledge that there is one hundred yields or 
establishes the knowledge that there is fifty-five. 

To this our reply is : quantitative reasoning is 
only a variety of inference. The inference here 
is as follows : ' Devadatta must own fifty-five, ^ 
because he owns one-hundred, just as I myself 

do/ .' "; y._;:\, 

There is another kind of knowing, viz., knoWr,J 
ing by the method of exhaustion. Thus whe^l 



f'Zl 



w + 



43, 7 



PRAMAtfACANDBIKA ,151 

by eliminating other possible alternatives one 
after another we arrive at the last or remaining 
alternative, our knowledge of the truth of this 
last alternative is gained by the method of exhaus- 
tion. It is of two kinds, viz., (1) that which 
proceeds by the method of affirmation, and (2) 
that which proceeds by the method of negation 
or exclusion. The former is illustrated in the 
following : — When we know that the two persons 
before us are Gaitra and Maitra, then the know- 
ledge, ' this one of the two persons is Caitra,' 
entails the knowledge, ' the other one is Maitra.' 
The second is illustrated in the following :«*r 
When we know that the two persons before us 
are Caitra and Maitra, then the knowledge, ' this 
one (of the two) is not Caitra ' entails the know- 
ledge, ' this, then, must be Maitra.' ■_-_ . - j; - 
This also, we hold, is a case of inferential 
knowledge. The inference is as follows : The 
disputed subject is Maitra, because, being either 
Gaitra or Maitra, he is not Caitra (in fact), just 
as is Gaitra (by agreement in absence). (In 
other words he who is not Maitra, is also not he 
who, being either Caitra or Maitra, is not Caitra, 
just as is Caitra, who is not Maitra and is also 
not he who, being either Caitra or Maitra, is not 
Caitra) Here to preclude the illegitimate exten- 
sion of the hetu to the cases of the jar, etc., the 
h^ords ' being either Caitra or Maitra ' have been 
included. _ 



-5- ■ v ** .-*■#>£ Ji-i •£■ *t- ; r^y* ^ - " " v ' *" 






16 




122 MADHVA LOGIC 

Upakrama, etc., are also forms of inference?! 
for they produce an inferential knowledge of the 
purport of sentences. An unbroken continuum of 
tradition without any known originator thereof is ^ 
Aitihya or Tradition- For example, the hearsay, g 
1 In this fig-tree lives a demon' (is a case of aitihya). r| 
This is nothing but verbal testimony (and should not 
count as an independent source of knowledge). "So f t 
also all the rest such as omens and signs (Sakuna) 9 
written language (Upi)> gesture language (cesta) . ■: 
—ail these as sources of knowledge are included 
in the forms of evidence (i.e., the three we have '_* 
explained) we have set forth above. We shall 
now explain the nature of validity itself . The 
intrinsic nature of validity is of two kinds? t>t0 M 

(1) intrinsicality in respect of origin (utpattt), 
and (2) intrinsicality in respect of verification ^ 
in consciousness (jiiapti). Of these, intrinsi 
cality in respect of origin means that the 
validity arises from the same conditions as 
cause the cognition itself of which the validity 
is a logical character. In other words, validity 
being an intrinsic or essential character of -a 
cognition in the matter of its origin means that 
the causes which produce a cognition are also 
the causes which produce the validity of the cogni- 
tion. By intrinsicality in respect of verification 
in knowledge is meant that the validity is apprefj 
hended by the same agency a& is. the cbgnitic 
itself of which it is a logical character, • Itt-^ 



^ 



••-. 



■::■■; 



* t 









PRAMAtfACANDRlKA 128 

w 

words, validity being an intrinsic or inherent 
character of a cognition in respect of its being 
known as such means that that which apprehends 
the cognition also apprehends the validity of the 
cognition. 

... The extrinsicality of invalidity is likewise 
of two kinds, viz., (1) extrinsicality in respect 
of the origin of the invalidity, and (2) ex- 
trinsicality in respect of its confirmation in 
consciousness as such. Of these, extrinsicality 
or adventitiousness in respect of origin means 
that the invalidity arises from conditions other 
than those which cause the cognition itself* 
Again, extrinsicality in respect of the invalidity 
being known as such means that the invalidity 
is cognised by an agency other than the agency 
which cognises or apprehends the cognition itself. 
Thus everything has been set forth in its proper 
place. 

- The Sankhya philosophers however hold that 
both validity and invalidity are intrinsic alike 
in respect of their origin and their being known 
as such. The Naiyayikas, on the contrary, 
hold that both are extrinsic. And they say 
in this connection that a cognition itself is 
caused by the sense-organs, etc., while the 
validity of the cognition is caused by the presence 
of certain specially efficacious qualities in the 
il causes of a cognition. Similarly, the 
didity of the cognition is due to the presence 






1 ■ r" *~\> •+. 



124 "MADHVA LOGIC *|, 

V, * ■ 

mm -^ 

* '*» 

of certain special defects or deficiencies in th#i 
causes of a cognition. And so also (in tito£ 
matter of being known) a cognition itself i»| 
cognised immediately by internal perception by tb#f| 
mind. But the validity of a cognition is 
cognised mediately by inference from the mark or j| 
sign of successful or unsuccessful practical re^;^ 
action. Thus the general condition (according to ]■■ 
NySya) of valid cognition is an efficacious quality 
(in the cause), and the general condition dfjjj 
invalid cognition is a certain defect or deficiency 
(in the cause). The Buddhists, again, say^T 
invalidity is intrinsic while validity is extrinsic^ 
But the real fact is, both the cognition and its] 
validity are caused by the sense-organs and the - 
rest. But the invalidity is generated by /&^ 
sense-organs, etc., together with certain defect^ 
as auxiliary conditions. Similarly, both theg; 
cognition and its validity are cognised immediate 
ly by the witnessing intelligence. But 
invalid cognition is cognised only as cogn 
by the witnessing intelligence. The invalidity 

of it is known mediately by inference from 
mark of practical unfruitfulness or failure. 

But it may be said : the position taken by 
the author here is not tenable. The author's v 
is : the agency which cognises the cognition a 
cognises the validity thereof. Further the po 
of the instruments of cognition to produce 
Cognition becomes the power to produce 






jPRAMi^ACANDRIKA l2§ 

* 

invalidity when aided by the special causes of 
invalidity. The power thus becomes as it were 
a different power through the influence of the 
defects in the matter of producing invalidity. 
Moreover, the cognition of these instruments 
takes place through a different agency, for the 
sense-organs, etc., are themselves cognised each 
by its own pramana or suitable knowing process 
(e.g., the sense-organs are cognised by inference 
from the results which their actions produce). At 
the same time their conduciveness to the production 
of valid knowledge is also cognised by inference 
(i.e., by another inference from the mark of 
practical f ruitf ulness) . But why should this be 
so? (i.e., Why should you suppose that the 
agency which cognises a cognition also cognises 
its validity, but the fitness of the sensibilities to 
'? produce a valid cognition is not cognised by the 
, : same agency, i.e., the inference that cognises the 
sensibilities themselves?) What is the bar to the 
supposition that the validity is cognised by an 
agency other than that which cognises the cognition 
(just as the fitness of the sensibilities is cognised 
t by an inference different from that which cognises 
the sensibilities themselves) ? ' . 

^ Our reply to this is : this cannot be admitted, 

I ; .because any such admission will entail an infinite 
regress. Thus we say : the validity of a valid 
I cognition must itself be cognised as such by 
I? „„™„ «.im virion, otherwise there will be no 



126 _ w MADHVA LOGIC 






valid cognition anywhere. And such validity 
cannot possibly be cognised by any agency other 
than that which cognises the cognition itself.. 
In the event of any other agency apprehending 
the validity, the validity of this apprehension will 
itself have to be apprehended by another (i.e., a 
third) apprehension, thus leading to an 
infinite regress. And if to avoid the infinite 
regress we say that the second cognition 
apprehending the validity of the primary cogni- 
tion is self-validating or self-evident, then sq 
may also be the primary cognition. There-? 
fore by the method of elimination of other;;- 
possible alternatives, the intrinsicality of validity 
is established as the only position that remains 
unshaken. It cannot be said that the objection 
of an infinite regress holds equally in respect ': 
of our view that the validity is imme* 
diately cognised by the witnessing Intelli- ; 
gence, for the witnessing Intelligence (in our 
view) is- self-revealing and as such reveals ■ 
both itself and its validity. But why not 
assume the same with regard to cognition 
also? Because, we reply, cognition being 
a state or function of the internal organ is non- 
intelligent and as such is incapable of self- 
illumination or self -revelation. The validity of 
the instruments should be understood on the 
lines of the Paddhati. Thus is everything beauti-i 
fully explained. 






■** Ui 



y\r: 



PRAllAtfACANDBIKA 

This brings the chapter on Iga 
Pramanacandrika by Srimacchalarifefi 

close. 

May the sage Sri Vedavyasa be pleas 




M^I*lNfe*l 



ire*r. ^rlr^: 




frft urannk 1*1 «**» *#^ w J*"" 

17 




130 



MADHVA LOGIC 



4IT4K3 T?W I ^flt 'TTOfa I irt^T'WTt^src : I rfSTfo 
«!el<tfd I BW «WUd*II ^lRpffet 4ld)«B& I WWt 

^rn^ff^ *fa ^4*ddiMi ^JufdUKctiifti*;; *3* 

* 

3T3W I H'*WdM'nJ<chlfd^l?BWiyK^y^iqMi.l3W' 



rftrr^r^«^«^i 











r: i mi 





e« 



*T- « 







PRAMA^ACANDRIKA 131 

* 

m^fai * foc&rd « mr« : I a«ift?iTra stow* fa « 
fifrramfri wraroi^i ^a i a* *fffS*9 **** 

i 

srafcs^ ^P^T^'wsnfir. i «* www 



-V * " 



132 



MADHVA LOGIC 



q*arq" W§ STW3TW Srffalfi I *S*«jTH*lfq W3T*l \ 

^wm^i^n f^ctft5H«e(i^ 1 *rt «sra *^# *ni 
qz *t> vrsis^rrfH*. 1 < nft#Bi^nn9»n#i^ im 1 

ni'wg* <NHHy*ft gjqz^WT^TT *?3TT> **I?T- 

ar^ara yg: fsjapn, sir $^fadi i n^Hfcfdmirn : 1 *ra1 

isr^juj 1 ?^ ^to^ MqqiTHTqT-resiaT: ^jiw- 
^T 1 i* tok^n&mi: #jrat tot 1 sn*- 





--"■*! 






PRAMAtfACANDRIKi 133 

xpjqt wst fMfafsreTOrat wugwfaflig* *i»*U<ff?«f 
*toAnjM*j«^ fam wrw- jprat ^ » ^rerarr^- 
Wfrawn'wi fdm!ij*^aiMd: «'swt *refo firatf 

TO Ut ^ ww ftft » ^^rf^w: ^>rat ami 

*rfafl «w2»Tt *?n*fa wh«1«iu<iw»wwH set i 
*»mt gznft*i ^5n«T^nqHH^<r*<rd i *pjq*w: 



134 MADHVA LOGIC 

<t.qfafd 1 CTflBV M*H*\y\^i>Tf\oH\VH: I *?«$<< WT3T- 

wroniirert *rai i ^^t *m ^ifa =^n^tf?r irans- 
g# *mra: i xstsrri«mrH$% I ?nr, ^fifsarre: i 



^/ 



"■Jfl 



* For the use of the word vfflpf in masculine, compare— 

<anr*ftsfa sr j'finrt ««*m«<: s^ffir a 

SarasvatiA:antJia6fearano, eh., 61. 70. 





X. 



PRAMA^ACANDRIKA 



135 



'j 



* ► 





Wt Jl^l^ t^ H«ltrt ff^T 

to. nHT^p^TOt^Jtra?T \fh %j, i i ?rerw«3sfa 

ijfoM m$l warrtmifkfow*: I to «'w- 
toto ftfro t^wgroro %fa i to *reT*i- 

I wt tm i ^faft » to>kto ifcHfof- 




: i 



s*wiR{«wir<i"«ifH; 



/♦ * 



to 



136 MADHVA LOGIC 



tow? ^rata^rawf? fa<* ^ « tfonmrw- 

aftnn* g Jprrcatsril^ i **mfa f^wlf <icn«*i i 
sfa tundra ^t^wssrcrafaiw wt mfe*- 




-■■ 



PRAMA^ACANDMKi 137 

trefwitf^fti wsst^i ynt^ T^n^ - 
W&wnfc <j**u Hih^wifrwaftiig- 





'V 



^ * r 



*" 







<#' 




'^"^^^"^^r 





f*^" -' - 



t 



■^sii 



# 



.vijrf^Be 



18 



138 



MADHVA LOGIC 








y 



K 




praMasacandrika 139 

?nrafc ?^T^t wrssmfon iw 

*3*ffignT «n«iMt ^ft?ro ftwn i ■«■* 
**« «M iW ^i**"™ *** **<**; 




140 



MADHVA LOGIC) 



m 



m 






/- >S 



*i, * '^ 



i 





?* 



^ 






PRAMAtfACANDRIKA 141 




*pi tut *w**rat: wrararcj. i rm ^w«m«ww 

cnra«ii «h«m<wW * < " l " ,ll "- Jll4J '...! 1 ?" 
iEww^a* ««M ***** wii^ fo*** * 




** 



-Ta. 



142 



V r 



MA.DHVA LOGIC 



> 



i* 



;* i 



I ?ra I TOT *afn wwi- 





1 - 

^gf*N lfSTO( I §TGTOT3W «P9ita<3TO #mwi 










5W 




^: wiitu 1 




Ml 



* 



y— 



^ 



i 









v 

.•.^r— 



4a 



FreK 






i *rat forbid i Tipnaw 

farot *nfm i to «wto tat: wfr ww- 

anting i aa wt «m: *f»a*W. i amrafe- 
aWfer aro tmPwfaiBftkJ faafwwj *ft * 











■;■*•*■« 



144 mIdhva logic •' " ; ;£| 

qrcqrarosnfafwnT i ?m*lf w$& &m 



- y. 




5Bsi*f v fentar tot ^*iwit*i«iw-»»w^| 
Sweeny i ** fi^i ?rar^«rsf«^ «fl»M| 

sb&^to^i *» w^sfa ***** 
fo mafafa sura: i «i«nfo<*w ?w sRwafafa 



* gfeas*r* ^fasmfvi ftft to: i 




PRAMA.NAGANDRIKA. 145 

3iTBi3TTirawT9: i **ra^wn*ni i «* m wa * 
qmaswaa: S**f^ **n^ m^ra 3^3- 

19 









3 



\8 



14G MADHVA LOGIC 

tm: i qa*n«wmi g ^TfinjTHdteufww: « ft 
sitow: * i ^erai: i *n ^: *t =! q?T wsan j 

41<Ud)fdf<!l$*r *Mfrd<4l * W[>sft w: Tift <- lfli " n 





3ft 



PkAMAtfACANDRIKA 147 

^%nt wff fore: i ^sf^fonw* *n«rcf*?T- 

smfa: i *rt. *nra§^tfii i *<re3fa *fa*wwfow 

«wwN4,fafo i tfsfawn w^^qf-^^- 
?ren»ta irf?rerat g^f^fcfa <m#*S*3fti i 

*ifirftife:i mr * f^ 5 ^ «* ***** 
**,, *m*z ifin " 9 ■***< ***** 




i48 MADHVA LOGIC 

i *refa * *nfo*?rr * w^fh tot t^m *fa arf?ft*- 

qrf«hrtre*n^ §^: ^RfaqwsjTafTSTWF* *fa ihfljj 
tot: «*i*dffiif<fd ^qiftrisfosrTfH: i *ra: vm- 

3fltapm I ?H^§ qlriV^ ^fe«*dt OTH^Tf^fe 



^ 



«■* 



***<. 




t-BAMA^ACANDEIKi 149 

?TH«ns3: l *? fs 3* ^T^l %feWT^ TOT 

WW I qtsfrWT^ T »T*f?l « W^l 1 «*fo TOT 

g^ i ^TfirroH&RftTOfaww ^ TO «ta «t* i 

W^fM « to t£* sntm i f*^ *nf*r?re*- 
wpi# i firnffiqfti^raa^ st ^foa«wi$*gii 
«at$g«r^i at st^itto ^nt^fNti§«TO i w»- 
*s^rf^ sgar wr« <*iirHr«*i*i*iyi TO*<ta 

?PH«1iTO^ar«TMi ft*«|i *PTO*af?tft%ftr 
g *fr wi i fiH«maifo i tTOt%asrra: «wtr 

Sfii i 

S^rcgnM ftfro ^ra <wro * ifiii to *ro 

q ianfaftfil *nt* *s*tar ?i^ffrf to?ttoW to: » 
nrt wiro «Ptot* * f* ^ ** wfin 
to fMMMMM ***** '***'** ^ 



150 



MA.DHVA LOGIC 



0\ 



iTTO *TWcf ^fai "BT*<*JrtJ^ I nr^mV 

wh<w<hhJ *$$& i treat ^%WT^ ^q-wic^ | 

forssw fea- q- ^ fg: i tot ^<wifcfd i srrtw- 

tot wJTTrjJna «i?H«: i 5^t?tfan*nfFrw , >ra^ 
twsBrer. tot fifewpra w&tf?. i *nffr- 

*mrafe«iiriifoiM ^ra^i^iHuj i tot qt w^H J 
^sfrwnr tot sirre ^fa i ^fa^STfinRsi'f- 

«T5[ a wMa « spur, a wfa tot WW* 

3RTctf ^r^gtrro: i ^arsta 

aa «m«w mvi twaTsfa mrfttn iwMf. 



--* 






■JE? 



-W 



'-'V* 



•■$? 



PRAHA^ACANDRIKA 



151 



fattarwfaj^Tct i aa f^t^fefw. i ufatnfaita- 
fgfafta-ssT'rTfaflwsTa, i aa wfrmfa^t ftrfar. i 

aa iresnmT'JrfMtasiteT^if g faaa fa^n, ssasiq, 
aisa afapan, am ssfarcsrafafa i *ra aa, az *arfi?- 
a?a%v, fawa a<a»i, *rata*ir<di<i, a«*faqaaf?eaT- 

gawarfefta t 5^: l wiawronfadawterf** 

i aaraOTas^ aafaqwraaV. 
anaia^ awa*?nmpirfa*Nt *Tasr. I *aaaafa*lat 
fefaa: j srofaaTaaarfaw^i i aa aafara- 

jaa at ro i ffteiflwKnw : i aa?- 

aTaaaa^rrta ^aaiftaaaa 

jt^ I aar (*Hlw<«u«yw«a' 

iti ^k: i *iaaa *a .«*wfiraHfc i aw 

fTTrTT 4%y<*i1< I 







^ngrfini 



152 MADHVA LOGIC 

*na afa a?«Taaa a*F«: ; wpww^wrmfH i aroit 
TOT si^tsfaa: n*\uvife fa I ftr^tat tot ais?t taar. 
3faai3Tf%fa i aatat tot aswtaaf «**ifefd i *re 
aaw a^caatwaawain ar% i 

ggi a i fa ftaT t%t%^: i aTvsaaanai anHl**i ^ta i 
*tt*i tot watsta<a ^aWi mwntf-ifo i tVata 
tot "aaaTaiTTa tot awta i 

aaraaf *W««ll<«ti4t<jfd | ^HTqfTfffWT^Tra 

aspRsrt^f?! i aiMir^ifac-^tis-faftfd a§r^>nt?ta i 

aa* guwra wwwh faqarcnwfa: aaTfaa- 
faaaca *nwfdmM' afa tat a«3 wfa I aaTiaa- 

cqfa3 :t a f <r . q^rfa faafearfa i %a3TTJataa^i ^wift 

^mfir i aw fannvnaa faqispsrreMceroTTaT^ i 

%rei *qftft£Mft sfo aiaTft ^sarfa, aw aqtSTMTaa w» 

awgqq'a: i aa faafisa'sqa, arfaaaatVaT: «nf«i«M- 
jfen faww. i a aTfaa-f2ra^Taant*r^irF^3raT- 
qf^-aiataqarw. q^ ^amrer: i sjnfipra^araa*:- 
faanai fgtfar. i a =a fafaa:, araaTtaa: uvufttV 
arracaTfaaafa i aaTaaTtaat fefaa: i wrsroa: 
faaaTaa i a ta i ^rrot tot i aaarctaaS ***** 
'a^^a^^TarttaFda'a^ i *ra aaareta'^araa:, * f 
aTaaa i taatat aaT i ata^iRa afa fawife* 



■■a 



*is 






PRAMltfACANDRIKA 153 

vravfti *"* *** ** ***** ^ T ^ fl ^ 

<$ fan* <msfo Wfcwwmwm 13 ;™*z 

ftmmor m fiwn* «**■*■*•*' 
rftritairt fern i «wfc ** <mr*TT*fc™ 







20 





. , .-. 3>& / ■ •>- 




154 MADHVA LOGIC 

^^^-HW^ira^rafH i *rrat m\— q&ft ««qi*i1*fl- 
«rnwg5?re:q^ 1 *ra ^f%5^r^ trow: 1 ^atiw- 

IK, — 

otllM^dt «H% I ?piT^ «uf*WHJcl 1 *rat wfr 

n<*rad erateriwn^fara ^rM«um<hm "shir i w 

H*\>M d^5d*&X|fafd ^rT^*toqTq^iffT llw I 

OS 

wftfa 1 w^mv^fi wifaft«*fsr *hi«j*iw1 -?WB" 



»■..-»(: 



■«.'. 






----- " * ■ k-5>5 




PRAMAljrACANDRiKA 155 

m n«mffl Sgfzrw. I *raT aj^ ftw 




*ra ^^nfq twani s^T^t *n% ' to *wwra: 

wanwrere* *w*rf to tort « '^^ [ 
gm sp^t fSrar: ^st^^^I «^**i ^V™. 



T^ 






156 



MADHVA LOGIC 







,., - -i 






:m 






M.i 



,/ 



■-03 



>/?^ 





ft** ft**; «* **^^ *™T? 



„- -v- --'' - "'• "" 






158 MADHVA LOGIC 

^3T ^STTf? I W*WP^lrfdMW*a^5re^ i&\- 

*ll4Ul<i «KTO ^^i^m ^ffqfa ; <afc<<i irf?r «uq I Mi- 
di!*^ dft ^Wddlq^SJ TWlt? | 

^|ch|§-T^ydwfafa*rTt a?Rt *RJ^t 3T3BP( I *P3 

«id«l*i3f9a f3R3TO^i tf^M^d f^fT fsfc<JI4iiHH4l«c|9- 
^tWT5|^iaf*T^IT5Wtr^^J 3dM^d W^FTf^ I 5P5T3T 

i^TT^r^ i mws ^k^: 3^t" 

^M«h<3*l «Icftl§-T ^§=31^ I d'Hfdm^ctftq^TOfa 

41«mi i ^ren si^h ftra^ga ; sra%^Tqt: ^iRraFW- 

^a ^ 5TC^q5T^ fd<q i^ <* JI MK : «WM l JHM 




-■?:* 



, ;m 



PBAMA^ACANDRIKA 159 

^Pwarq , i 4»«*wi ■4iiiwa' *&&m: *rasfa 7i^nfiw. 
f^fajK i sgwqt ^r^ir. i *ra wrfaw^: sj^jreftrf'iftrfr- 
*rat^^ " ^d^j gtMi-^i^fH maririts^. unfair 

q fa^qi^fe gg K^ifc^frffi l ^ rata i am ft 

firero ^t «b «ikBm i to *gs*f *ra attf *nar ** 
fctra a «n?fw «*<«a » MHmwnft« Tfe i a*r 3* 




160 



MADHTA LOGIC 



« n ftft» i * qf qi »w«*ici fate *ptoto « it arar^fa- 
■vm°i<^ nfwftfsr *are?r wrf. I wi «w 

sftrfif fro i gwsgw ^fo ' *a sifawsi 
%fa i ?ra <ti<«iid«iM4ii«Tn: ?ra «w^rr 



■ *'^- 



, v-- 









'^1 



,3& 





PRAMA^TACANDRIKA 161 

BZJtsRlWltsfa Kd\4WI«MI<l **«w«-*i3 I liflUi 

frni i i^m*n *ffa qfrpwn t^it writ «*n: i 
yprfll ftf*nit ^t fogtsfa^Hfa ^ i 

3<.Himw*i S 9 1 iNh vn^ *^ ■ 
3i5 «te ^^^ sraw^raTq. *ifcKWifc*i+i- 

IIWT^I rl^^sfq qfl3Tgq«PWT?l, fWSlWITW- 

^f^fa %9 i 3<r. wrote ^rotafcraracrei 39fnt%- 
**taWRn?ftfa f faftwiq , i * *^ : V*™ 

^irf^jt 'tr^rw^ ?R5^m^ *<|g*snft- 

unmwnwni m ft» ft^t fcft« 

*ntfra: qfhn«i i ww lismw *** ' 



Sjfe^iS -^ wi*r. < **nf*: *«^ "«*" *** 
21 



162 



MADHVA LOGIC 







1 fij ^CTTWilRj*!^ 



3*T fif«KiHii4i«i; TOW 



#1 ^ifdftaf f* 

* w* 



■\:: 



:*\ 






M 



■^i 



.'■■m 



* ^wts^Hiw Pro *S3 to: ^r^E^i fafriwiKict to*'*; t 
t wm; (?) 




■-.,.-: 



pramai*acandjukI 163 

WoM^gwR q^Rwfcnt i "tat ^%^ <*tas* «f?r 



^^reaR^^rss^fsrefa'^ Monism i *rarft 








■4 




164 MADHVA LOGIC 

^#rt%^ ^a^f^fa (rat%rcra: i ■erCTft atitaf- 
Sfnwii wra it ftrarrfts#f?f ^twi i <^r»mipi 



* ftnri^ *f?r g sfets'a* its: i 



PRAMA^ACANDRIKA 165 

sp*w| i 5N wf srra3 3^3 ffffl nroro strcra *far i 










166 



MADHVA LOGIC 



<iw<inEtRwm i3 far *rW«r?i #sr i jraras*- 



m 



f '-**.'! 



wwwaf St *rm$ <ict q* wra*?wi*«ra fl^terer ^insrw w^